Technophilosophy (or technological philosophy) may be
defined in a variety of ways. It may include the philosophy of technology (“tech
philosophy”), the philosophy of engineering, the philosophy
of computer science, and cyberphilosophy, as well as technofeminism, technocultural futurism
(including Afrofuturism, Latin@futurism, and other futurisms), and other cultural or
aesthetic movements embracing the philosophy of technology, the philosophy of science,
and social philosophy.
It may also be a philosophy based
on, or supported by, technology. Thus, it may be a philosophy founded on, or supported by, computers.
It may also be a philosophy aimed at
promoting the use of technology (in various settings and in society as a whole).
It may also be the philosophy of a
technological society or era.
It may also be a philosophy inspired
by technology. Thus, it may be a
philosophy of the technological self (e.g. the online identity, anonymity, or reality of
the self) and technological others. It may also be a philosophy of the machine
(e.g. regarding the ability of machines to think or to act intelligently) and machine-like
beings.
Technophilosophy may also be any
philosophy disseminated by technological means (e.g. by online philosophy encyclopedias, journals, blogs, podcasts, or videos). Thus, it may be an electronic or
e-philosophy, an integral component of the world of e-books, e-learning, and other online technology.
Technophilosophy may also be a
discipline analogous to technoart, technodance, technomusic, technoscience (including technobiology, technochemistry, and technophysics), and technopolitics.
It may be conventional or
unorthodox, aboveground or underground.
Technophilosophy (and the philosophy of technology) may include the study of the ethics, aesthetics, metaphysics, epistemology, and politics of technology. Thus, technophilosophy may include technoethics, technoaesthetics, technometaphysics, technoepistemology, and technopolitics.
Peter A. Angeles (1992) explains that
in ancient Greek philosophy, techne (art, skill, or craft) referred to (1)
anything deliberately created by humans, in contrast to anything not humanly
created, (2) any skill in making or doing things, (3) knowledge of how to do or
make things, as opposed to knowledge of why things are as they are, and (4)
professional knowledge of the procedures involved in making or doing
things. Such terms as “technique," “technical,” and “technology”
are derived from the Greek concept of techne.1
Technology is pervasive in modern
culture and society. Thus, the philosophy of technology may include the study
of agricultural, educational, energy, and environmental technology, as
well as film and video, financial, communications, medical,
military, and space technology.
Philosophers of technology include
Plato (Laws), Aristotle (Physics), Francis Bacon (New Atlantis, 1627), Ernst Kapp
(Grundlinien einer Philosophie der Technik, 1877), José Ortega y Gasset (Meditación de la técnica, 1939,
translated as “Thoughts on Technology,” 1972), Martin Heidegger (Die Frage nach der Technik, translated
as “The Question Concerning Technology,” 1977), and Lewis Mumford (Technics and Civilization, 1934).
Philosophers of technology also include Marshall McLuhan (Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, 1964), Michel Foucault (Technologies of the Self, 1988), Donna Haraway (Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature, 1991), Avital Ronell (The Telephone Book: Technology—Schizophrenia—Electric Speech, 1989), Don Ihde (Technics and Praxis, 1979; Bodies in Technology, 2001), Jacques Ellul (The Technological Society, 1964), Carl Mitcham (Thinking through Technology: The Path between Engineering and Philosophy, 1994), Fernando Broncano (Nuevas Meditaciones sobre la Técnica, 1995; Mundos Artificiales: Filosofía del Cambio Technológico, 2000), and Shannon Vallor (Technology and the Virtues: A Philosophical Guide to a Future Worth Wanting, 2016).
Philosophers of technology also include Marshall McLuhan (Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, 1964), Michel Foucault (Technologies of the Self, 1988), Donna Haraway (Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature, 1991), Avital Ronell (The Telephone Book: Technology—Schizophrenia—Electric Speech, 1989), Don Ihde (Technics and Praxis, 1979; Bodies in Technology, 2001), Jacques Ellul (The Technological Society, 1964), Carl Mitcham (Thinking through Technology: The Path between Engineering and Philosophy, 1994), Fernando Broncano (Nuevas Meditaciones sobre la Técnica, 1995; Mundos Artificiales: Filosofía del Cambio Technológico, 2000), and Shannon Vallor (Technology and the Virtues: A Philosophical Guide to a Future Worth Wanting, 2016).
José Ortega y Gasset (1939) defines
technology as the improvement brought about by us on nature for the
satisfaction of our necessities.2 It is also a reform of those
aspects of nature that place us in need. Thus, the concept of human necessity
is fundamental to our understanding of technology.3 The mission of
technology consists in releasing us for the task of being ourselves.4
Michel Foucault (1988) says there
are four major types of techniques or technologies that we can use to
understand ourselves: (1) technologies of production, which permit us to
produce, transform, or manipulate things, (2) technologies of sign systems,
which permit us to use signs and symbols to communicate meanings, (3)
technologies of power, which determine our conduct and submit us to certain
ends, and (4) technologies of the self, which permit us “to effect by [our] own
means or with the help of others a certain number of operations on [our] own
bodies and souls, conduct, and way[s] of being, so as to transform [ourselves]
in order to attain a certain state of happiness, purity, wisdom, perfection, or
immortality.”5
Foucault says these four types of technologies hardly ever function separately, although each of them may imply a
certain mode of training or modification, not only in the sense of our acquiring certain
skills, but also in the sense of our acquiring certain attitudes.6
Carl Mitcham (1994) distinguishes between the engineering philosophy of
technology and the humanities philosophy of technology. The former begins with an analysis of the nature of technology itself, while the latter begins with an analysis of the relation of technology to art, literature, ethics, politics,
and religion.7
Thomas A.C. Reydon (2018) describes
three approaches to (or ways of conceiving) the philosophy of technology: (1)
as systematic clarification of the nature of technology, (2) as systematic
reflection on the consequences of technology for human life, and (3) as
systematic investigation of the practices of engineering, invention, designing,
and making of things.8
Frederick Ferré
(1995) describes a number of possible questions regarding the use of current technologies,
such as (1) What should be the role of technology such as robotics and
automation in the workplace? (These technologies may in
some cases cause workers to lose their jobs, their sense of personal
autonomy, or their input regarding their job duties.) (2) What are the risks of relying completely on computers? (In addition to security and privacy concerns, there may be concerns regarding responsibility for error when computers are required to make important decisions.) (3) What limits should be set on the development of nuclear technology? (4) What kinds of technologies need to be transferred to developing countries? (5) What limits should be imposed on genetic engineering and the development of reproductive technology?9
David E. Nye (2006) asks, “Do we
control technology or does technology control us?” Do we shape the machines and
systems that surround us or are we shaped by them? (According to social
constructivists, technology is shaped by us, but according to technological determinists
or constructivists, we are determined or shaped by technology.) Are we using
technology to destroy the natural world or to protect it? Are we trying through
technology to undermine democracy or to enhance it? Are we trying to make the
world more secure or to make it more dangerous?10
Concerns that may arise regarding
the use of new or existing technologies include their ability to fulfill particular needs, their impact on quality of
life, their impact on human health, their impact on social equity (who will
benefit from them, and who won’t?), their expense, their
cost effectiveness, their ability to support economic growth, their environmental sustainability, their use of
renewable or nonrenewable natural resources, and their energy efficiency.
The risks of technology may include
the rise of a technocracy (a non-elected ruling class of technicians or a
technoelite) whose decisions can, or could, in innumerable ways, impact our daily lives. In
politics, a technocracy (as opposed to a democracy, but perhaps in some ways
similar to an aristocracy or plutocracy) might take the form of a government
ruled or dominated by a class of technological executives or corporate directors. A
technocracy might also be a government based on or guided by technological
principles, or a form of control of (public, social, and cultural) resources and institutions by technological executives, companies, or industries.
Technophilosophy should therefore
not be left to fall into the hands of a wealthy and powerful technoelite.
Technophilosophy may be avant-garde or futuristic in its embrace of technology and its interest in finding new ways of doing philosophy, but it should not
avoid the responsibility to recognize and attempt to remediate social and
cultural factors that contribute to inequitable access to technology. Another
responsibility of technophilosophy may be that of recognizing, questioning, and
challenging the methods by which technology becomes a means of social
control.
Other risks or possible pitfalls for
technophilosophy (and for philosophy of technology) include technicism and
technocentrism. Technicism, as defined by Egbert Schuurman (1997), is the
attitude that all problems can be solved by scientific-technological methods.11
(Technicism may be analogous to scientism, the attitude that all questions can
be answered, and all problems can be solved, by scientific methods.) Schuurman
explains that among the risks of technicism in the field of genetic engineering
are that it may result in the technicization of living organisms, resulting in
the loss of genetic and bio-diversity. This may in turn lead to a possible increase in susceptibility
of genetically engineered organisms to unknown diseases. If we accept the
technological model for plants, animals, and human beings, says Schuurman, then
we may see them merely as technological artifacts that we can manipulate, and
we may neglect their dignity and integrity.12
Technocentrism, as defined by to Seymour
Papert (1988), is the attitude that all questions center on the uses of
technology.13 Technocentrism may focus on technological solutions to
educational, economic, social, and cultural problems, to the extent that it disregards or neglects non-technological kinds of solutions.
Cyberphilosophy has been described as
the intersection of philosophy and computing.14 Cyberphilosophy may
include cyberethics (including the ethics of hacking, identity theft, violations of privacy, and so on), cyberaesthetics (including the aesthetics of computer hardware,
architecture, programming, and website design), cybermetaphysics (concerning the
nature of cyberspace, computer-generated worlds, and virtual reality),
cyberepistemology (concerning the relation between computing and the theory
of knowledge, and also concerning the kind of collective building and sharing of
knowledge that’s represented by openly editable websites like Wikipedia), cyberpolitics
(including cyberactivism, journalism, and blogging regarding such issues
as internet censorship, access, and net neutrality), and cyberphilosophy of
mind (including examination of the relation between computation and thinking or
consciousness). Cyberphilosophy may also be concerned with human-computer interaction, and with cyberculture
studies.
Technofeminism, according to Judy
Wajcman (2004), may examine the role that gender plays in technology and the
ways in which technology is gendered. It may also investigate and interrogate
the sexual politics of technology, and it may examine the relationship between
woman and machine.15
The technosphere (the technological
context in which we live16) consists of all the structures we’ve
built in order to help us survive on the planet.17 It includes such
structures as highways, buildings, machines, tools, equipment, and computer systems. The
other spheres of the Earth are the lithosphere (the solid surface layer of
the Earth), the atmosphere (the layer of air that stretches above the
lithosphere), the hydrosphere (the Earth’s water—on the surface, in the ground,
and in the air), and the biosphere (the part of the lithosphere, hydrosphere,
and atmosphere that supports life). The physical technosphere includes the urban, rural, subterranean, marine,
and aerial technospheres. Components of the technosphere include artifacts that
may eventually become technofossils (preserved material remains of
technological artifacts, which we may find nearly everywhere).18
FOOTNOTES
1Peter A. Angeles, The HarperCollins Dictionary of Philosophy (New York: HarperCollins
Publishers, 1992), p. 308.
2José Ortega y Gasset, “Thoughts on
Technology” [1939], in Philosophy and
Technology: Readings in the Philosophical Problems of Technology, edited by
Carl Mitcham and Robert Mackey (London:
Collier Macmillan Publishers, 1972), p. 292.
3Ibid.,
p. 294.
4Ibid.,
p. 300.
5Michel Foucault, “Technologies of the Self,” in Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with
Michel Foucault, edited by Luther H. martin, Huck Gutman, and Patrick H.
Hutton (London: University of Massachusetts Press, 1988, p. 18.
6Ibid.,
p. 18.
7Carl Mitcham, Thinking through Technology: The Path
between Engineering and Philosophy (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1994), p. 62.
8Thomas A.C. Reydon, “Philosophy of Technology,”
in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ISSN 2161-0002,
https://www.iep.utm.edu/, 2018.
9Frederick Ferré, Philosophy of Technology (Athens: The
University of Georgia Press, 1995).
10David E. Nye, Technology Matters: Questions to Live With (Cambridge: The MIT
Press, 2006), p. x.
11Egbert Schuurman, “Philosophical and Ethical
Problems of Technicism and Genetic Engineering,” in Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology, Fall
1997, Vol. 3, No. 1, online at https://scholar.lib.vt.edu/ejournals/SPT/v3n1/schuurman.html.
12Ibid.
13Seymour
Papert, “A Critique of Technocentrism in Thinking About the School of the
Future,” in Children in the Information
Age, 1988, pp. 2-18, online at http://www.papert.org/articles/ACritiqueofTechnocentrism.html.
14James H. Moor and Terrell Ward Bynum,
“Introduction to Cyberphilosophy,” in Metaphilosophy,
Vol. 33, Nos. 1/2, January 2002, p. 26.
15Judy
Wajcman, Technofeminsim (Malden:
Polity Press, 2004).
16Ferré, Philosophy of Technology
(Athens: The University of Georgia Press, 1995), p. 1.
17University of
Leicester, “Earth’s ‘technosphere’ now weighs 30 trillion tons, research
finds,” Nov. 30, 1016, Phys.Org,
online at https://phys.org/news/2016-11-earth-technosphere-trillion-tons.html.
18Jan Zalasiewicz,
et al., “Scale and Diversity of the Physical Technosphere: A Geological
Perspective, “ in The Anthropocene Review,
Vol. 4, Issue 1, Nov. 28, 2016, pp. 9-22.