Philosophy as performance may take the form of reading,
interpreting, discussing, arguing about, and responding to philosophical ideas
and texts. It may involve a single performer or multiple performers, and it may
take place in a library, in a classroom, on a stage, behind
a lectern, in a lecture hall, in a café, in a theater, beside a water fountain, in the midst of a
crowd, on a park bench, or on a rooftop.
Philosophy as performance may
incorporate aspects of not only the performing arts, but also the visual arts and
literary arts. Examples of performance philosophy include the public lectures and readings of the philosopher Alphonso Lingis, which have
included a stage performance in which he read a philosophical text while
dressed as a Geisha (in an art gallery in Kyoto, Japan, January 20, 1997).1
Another example of performance philosophy is the work of the artist and
philosopher Adrian Piper, whose conceptual art projects have included “The Mythic Being” (1973), a photo and film documentation of a street performance in which
she disguised herself as a man (donning an Afro wig, fake mustache, and
sunglasses) and recited mantras such as “I am the locus of consciousness” as she
walked through crowds of
onlookers.2
To describe philosophy as performance
is to describe a discipline whose potential to become a widely recognized
art form may not yet have been fully realized. Performance philosophy may involve
the use of multiple media, such as text, audio, video, background music, and
background lighting. It may also involve the wearing of makeup, wigs, and
costumes, the use of hand-held or stage props, the use of mobile stage platforms, the use of lighting and sound
effects, and the use of special effects (such
as optical and atmospheric effects) if they enhance and do not distract from the
presentation of philosophical ideas and texts.
More traditional performance
philosophy may include public readings of philosophical texts, panel discussions
of philosophical issues and problems, philosophical dialogues, philosophical
debates, and public conversations, colloquia, and symposia concerning
philosophical matters and subjects.
Whenever a philosopher addresses an
audience, teaches students, shares her work with colleagues, writes an
essay, publishes a book, interprets the work of another philosopher, or
answers the questions of an interviewer, she is in some way delivering a kind
of performance, insofar as she is presenting herself, her ideas, and her work
in a particular form or manner. She is in some way presenting, staging, framing, or displaying aspects of herself (such as her personal and professional habits, her conversational style, her writing style, her research methods, and
her philosophical interests and concerns). Her performance of herself and of her
ideas or work may be more or less spontaneous or
deliberate, committed or uncommitted, self-conscious or unself-conscious, intentional or unintentional.
The way in which a philosopher
presents her ideas, thoughts, and impressions to a reading, listening, or
viewing audience involves a kind of performance of those ideas, thoughts, and
impressions in order to connect with, and engage, the audience. It also
involves a kind of performance of herself in the role of philosopher, in order
to gain the audience’s acceptance, attention, engagement, trust, and respect. It also
involves a kind of performance on the part of the audience, insofar as it must
interpret and determine how to respond to the philosopher’s ideas, thoughts, and
impressions. Each of these three kinds of performance may be relatively felicitous or infelicitous, successful or unsuccessful, skillful or unskillful.
Philosophy as performance may be
planned, memorized, scripted, and rehearsed, or it may be unplanned,
unmemorized, unscripted, and unrehearsed. It may be linear or non-linear,
monologic or dialogic, interactive or non-interactive.
To see philosophy as performance may
be to see that philosophy must recognize its own performativity. The
performativity of philosophy may arise from the kinds of social roles that
philosophy performs, and from the kinds of social roles that philosophers play when
they do philosophy. The act of doing philosophy may be both performative and
constative in nature.
Philosophy may
theorize performance, and it may analyze the relation between performance and
performativity. To explore philosophy as performance, we may need to explore
not only the discursive and representational, but also the non-discursive and
presentational modes of philosophical speech and language.
Performativity may be defined as the
state of being a performance. It may also be defined as the ability to perform
an action, role, duty, purpose, or function. The degree to which something
(such as an utterance, segment of discourse, mode of behavior, or mode of language)
is a performance (or is performative) determines the degree of its performativity.
Performativity may also be defined
as the quality of being a performative utterance. A performative utterance
is an utterance that does not describe or report anything, but that
nevertheless performs some social role or function.3 Performative
utterances include acts of apologizing, thanking, ordering, promising, welcoming,
warning, admitting, approving, and disapproving. For example, the utterance,
“Be careful” performs the role of an admonition, and the utterance “Excuse me”
performs the role of a request for pardon.
Performances may be live or
recorded. While a recorded performance may look or sound the same each time it
is repeated, a live performance may never look or sound the same each time it is repeated. Each time a philosopher presents a live performance of
her work to an audience, she may be performing that work in a somewhat different
manner, and each time an audience sees or listens to that work, it may be responding
to it in a somewhat different manner.
Performance and philosophy may be
two sides of the same coin. Thus, we have on one side of the coin/and on the
other side of the coin:
Performance as Philosophy/Philosophy
as performance
The performer as philosopher/The
philosopher as performer
The philosophy of performance/The
performance of philosophy
The philosophy of art/The art of philosophy
Art as philosophy/Philosophy as art
The artist as philosopher/The philosopher as
artist
Conceptual art as philosophy/Philosophy as
conceptual art
The comedy of philosophy/The philosophy of
comedy
The tragedy of philosophy/The philosophy of
tragedy
Philosophy as jazz/Jazz as philosophy
Philosophy as the blues/The blues as
philosophy
Poetry as philosophy/Philosophy as poetry.
Performance as Philosophy/Philosophy
as performance
The performer as philosopher/The
philosopher as performer
The philosophy of performance/The
performance of philosophy
The philosophy of art/The art of philosophy
Art as philosophy/Philosophy as art
The artist as philosopher/The philosopher as
artist
Conceptual art as philosophy/Philosophy as
conceptual art
The comedy of philosophy/The philosophy of
comedy
The tragedy of philosophy/The philosophy of
tragedy
Philosophy as jazz/Jazz as philosophy
Philosophy as the blues/The blues as
philosophy
Poetry as philosophy/Philosophy as poetry.
When we study performance as
philosophy, we must ask ourselves: Is there a philosophy that produces the
performance, or does the performance itself produce a philosophy? What makes a
performance a work of art? What makes a performance philosophical?
Other questions that must be
considered include: Can a
philosophical text, reading, or interpretation be considered a work of art? Can
Plato and Aristotle be performed in some way that is analogous to the way in
which Mozart and Shakespeare can be performed? Is Plato’s interpretation of
Socrates in some way analogous to Bernstein’s interpretation of Mahler or
Gould’s interpretation of Bach? Is philosophical interpretation in some way
analogous to literary, musical, or dramatic interpretation?
And still other questions that may need to be considered include: Is there a performance philosophy that is analogous to performance poetry? Can performance philosophy take the form of spoken word poetry? Is performance philosophy a philosophy of performance, or is it philosophy as performance?
Some adjectives that may be used to
describe a performance, when it is praiseworthy, include “impressive,” “outstanding,”
“remarkable,” “extraordinary,” “powerful,” “moving,” “amusing,” and “entertaining.”
Some adjectives that may be used to describe a performance, when it is not so praiseworthy,
include “average,” “mediocre,” “amateurish,” “overwrought,” “annoying,”
“tedious,” “mechanical,” “stiff,” and “boring.” The kinds of adjectives that may be used to describe praiseworthy or unpraiseworthy performances indicate
the kinds of performances that performers may want, or may not want, to give.
There may be a philosophy of each of the performing arts, i.e. a philosophy of music, a philosophy of dance, a philosophy
of drama, a philosophy of performance art, a philosophy of public speaking, and so on. However, all these
philosophies may share a concern with such questions as: How should art be
defined? How is art created? What makes art inspiring or uninspiring? What kinds of truth does art reveal? What kinds of meaning does art express? What kinds of
response may art evoke in an audience?
Conceptual art may be philosophical
in its themes and content. Examples include Joseph Kosuth’s "One and Three Chairs" (1965), Jenny Holzer’s “Truisms” (1984), and Barbara Kruger’s “Belief+Doubt”
(2012). Performance art may also be philosophical in its themes and content.
Examples include Pope.L’s “Tompkins Square Crawl” (1991), Maren Hassinger’s “Women’s Work” (2006), and Marina Abramović’s
“The Artist is Present” (2010).
FOOTNOTES
1Clark Lunberry, “The Philosopher and the Geisha: Alphonso Lingis and the Multi-Mediated Performance of Philosophical Discourse," in Discourse, Vol. 22, No. 2 (Spring 2000), pp. 92-103.
FOOTNOTES
1Clark Lunberry, “The Philosopher and the Geisha: Alphonso Lingis and the Multi-Mediated Performance of Philosophical Discourse," in Discourse, Vol. 22, No. 2 (Spring 2000), pp. 92-103.
2Robin Cembalest, “Adrian Piper Pulls Out of
Black Performance-Art Show,” in ArtNews,
Oct. 25, 2013, online at http://www.artnews.com/2013/10/25/piper-pulls-out-of-black-performance-art-show/.
3J.L.
Austin, How to do things with Words
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1962).
No comments:
Post a Comment