With the very first paragraph of Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979), Richard Rorty's conception of epistemology starts to go astray, as he begins his criticism of traditional
epistemology by saying that such philosophers as Descartes, Locke, Kant, Russell, and Husserl have sought to adjudicate claims to knowledge by trying to define the
“foundations” of knowledge. Rorty says that if knowledge is seen as being based
on accurate mental representations of the world, then the mind may be seen as a
mirror of nature, and philosophy’s task may be seen as that of adjudicating knowledge
claims by judging the accuracy of their representations of reality. He criticizes
this mentalist and representationalist approach to the theory of knowledge,
saying that epistemology as it has, in his view, traditionally been practiced
(as a theory of representation) should be abandoned.
Rorty conflates the search for the
“foundations” of knowledge with the search for the “conditions” of knowledge,
however. The distinction between the two is important, although he might
deny this and might say that the conditions of knowledge are merely
foundational principles of knowledge. There is a difference, however, between
seeking to establish certain basic or foundational truths and seeking to
establish the conditions under which those basic or foundational truths may be known.
While the “foundationalist” approach may seek to define certain basic truths or
knowledge claims on which other truths or knowledge claims can be based, the “conditionalist”
approach may seek to define the necessary and sufficient conditions under which truth or knowledge claims can be made. Rorty identifies epistemology with
foundationalism, and he therefore rejects it. But his critique of epistemology amounts
to a kind of straw man argument. He criticizes epistemology for being something
that it is not (al least not in the view of many classical and modern
philosophers).
This is not to say that epistemology
is merely an attempt to define the conditions of knowledge. It is much more
than that. It's also concerned with the nature, extent, and limits of human knowledge,
the formulation and communication of knowledge, and the differences between
knowledge and belief, opinion, faith, and imagination.
Alan Malachowsksi (1990) explains
that Rorty also tends to conflate the notion that it is unwise to crave for a
theory of knowledge with the notion that it is unwise to think of knowledge as
something that has or needs foundations, and that Rorty fails to establish the truth of either of these notions.1 Since
Rorty also claims that it’s unwise to pursue an epistemologically-centered philosophy,
Malachowski says that it’s fair to ask whether Rorty’s views actually amount to a
substantive position on epistemology, and that this may indeed be a difficult
question to answer.2
Descartes (1641) is a
foundationalist, insofar as he argues that we can know the truth of things if
we have clear and distinct ideas about them. He says there are
innate ideas in the human mind that are independent of our own perceptions and our
own will. All innate ideas are clear and distinct, but adventitious ideas
derived from our perceptions and factitious ideas derived from our illusions or
imaginations may be unclear and indistinct.
Locke (1689) is also a
foundationalist, insofar as he describes three “degrees” of knowledge:
intuitive, demonstrative, and sensory. According to Locke, intuitive knowledge
is an immediate perception of the agreement or disagreement of two or more
ideas, without the intervention of any other ideas. Demonstrative knowledge is
a perception of the agreement or disagreement or two or more ideas, based on
proofs provided by intervening ideas. Sensory knowledge is a perception of the
agreement or disagreement of two or more ideas, based on sensory experience of
the external objects to which those ideas refer. Demonstrative knowledge is
based on intuitive knowledge, and intuitive certainty is required for every
step of reasoning that produces demonstrative certainty. The faculty of
understanding is necessary, however, in order to combine the three degrees of
knowledge (intuition, demonstration, and sensation) into a more unified and
comprehensive knowledge that transcends the respective limits of reason, intuition, and
experience.
Hume (1739) is also a foundationalist, insofar as he says that all ideas are originally derived from sensory
perceptions, and that knowledge is ultimately based on experience rather than
reason. Hume says that in order to establish the existence of an object, we
must have already had a sensory perception of that object or of other objects
from which the existence of that object can be inferred. Reason alone is
insufficient to establish the existence of an object; sensory perception of
that object, directly or indirectly, is necessary.
Russell (1913) is also a
foundationalist, insofar as he says that knowledge is based on acquaintance
with self-evident truths. According to Russell, true propositions that are not
self-evident must, in order to become objects of knowledge, be demonstrated to
be true by self-evident propositions.. Knowledge is based on acquaintance with
self-evident propositions and with propositions whose truth can be demonstrated
by self-evident propositions.
Carnap (1924) is also a
foundationalist, insofar as he says that all scientific statements are
reducible to structural statements about basic elements of experience. According
to Carnap, structural statements are logical propositions about the formal
properties of objects or relations. A constructional system of reality is a
system in which the objects of each level are constructed from objects of more
elementary levels of construction. The most elementary level of a
constructional system is the level of basic objects, which includes basic
elements and basic relations. The basic elements of a constructional system are
“elementary experiences” that are not constructed but are immediately given to
consciousness as formal objects.
The “conditionalist” philosophers, on the other hand, may include Plato, Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Schopenhauer, and others.
For Plato, belief, truth, and
justification are conditions of knowledge. True beliefs constitute knowledge if
they can be logically justified. In response to the kinds of counterexamples
supplied by Edmund Gettier (1963) of cases in which justified true beliefs may
not constitute knowledge, many contemporary philosophers have proposed immunity to Gettier
cases as another condition of knowledge. This subject has been discussed by
such philosophers as Chisholm (1989), Lehrer (1990), Zagzebski (1994), Sosa (2011), Turri (2011), and Dretske (2015).
Kant (1781) may be both a
foundationalist, insofar as he calls for a critique of pure reason in order to
determine the possibility, principles and extent of a priori knowledge, and a conditionalist, insofar as he attempts to
describe the conditions under which a
priori knowledge is possible. He provides a table of twelve categories or pure
concepts of the understanding, describing them as a priori concepts that define conditions of possible experience.
These categories or pure concepts of the understanding also define conditions
under which the content of intuitions and representations may be unified by the
understanding.
Fichte (1794-95)
claims that the first, absolutely unconditioned principle of the science of
knowledge is the act by which the self becomes conscious of itself. The second
principle, conditioned as to content, is the act by which the non-self is
opposed to the self. The third principle, conditioned as to form, is the act by
which the self and non-self are posited as divisible so that a limited self may
be opposed to a limited non-self.
Schelling (1800)
argues that transcendental idealism is a system for all knowledge, and that it affirms
that a transcendental unity of the self and nature, the subjective and
objective, and the conscious and unconscious is a condition of knowledge.
Schopenhauer (1818) says that
transcendental idealism affirms that a transcendental unity of reason and
experience is the condition for knowledge. He also says that all knowledge,
except for knowledge of Platonic Ideas, depends on the principle of sufficient
reason, and that the conditions for knowledge of Platonic Ideas include pure
contemplation, extinction of desire, transcendence of the subject-object relation, and freedom from confinement by individuality.
Rorty describes epistemology as a
discipline concerned with the possibility of accurate representation, as if
most epistemologists have already agreed that this is what epistemology is, and as if
this is all it can be. In his view, if knowledge is not a matter of accurate
representation, then we have no more need of epistemology. But this is a very skeptical and simple-minded view of epistemology. Does Rorty actually
believe that a theory of accurate representation is all that epistemology can
be? Is he perhaps being intentionally obtuse and simplistic for the sake of
provoking some sort of critical response?
His position also seems
to be that to debunk Cartesian mind-body dualism is to debunk epistemology.
He criticizes the concept of
philosophy as a foundational discipline for other disciplines, as a discipline
that can adjudicate the procedures and truth claims of other disciplines. He also
criticizes the concept of philosophy as a discipline that “takes as its study
the ‘formal’ or ‘structural’ aspects of our beliefs,” serving “the cultural
function of keeping other disciplines honest” by “limiting their claims to what
can be properly ‘grounded.’”3
There may, however, exist within
epistemology viable alternatives to foundationalism, which Rorty doesn't seem
to account for. For example, Keith Lehrer (1990) explains that the explanatory
coherence theory of justification (that justification is a reciprocal relation
of coherence among beliefs belonging to a system) may be an alternative to the
foundation theory (that some beliefs are completely justified in themselves and
can therefore serve as the foundation for the justification of other beliefs).4 Rorty comes close to acknowledging this when he says, "For the Quine-Sellars approach to epistemology, to say that truth and knowledge can only be judged by the standards of the inquirers of our own day is not to say that human knowledge is less noble or important...than we had thought. It is merely to say that nothing counts as justification unless by reference to what we already accept, and that there is no way to get outside of our own beliefs and our language so as to find some test other than coherence."5
Infinitism (the theory that beliefs may be justified for an infinite number of reasons) may be another alternative to the foundation theory.
Infinitism (the theory that beliefs may be justified for an infinite number of reasons) may be another alternative to the foundation theory.
FOOTNOTES
1Alan R. Malachowski, “Deep Epistemology without
Foundations (in Language),” in Reading
Rorty: Critical Responses to Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (and Beyond),
edited by Alan R. Malachowski (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, Ltd., 1990), pp.
140-141.
2Ibid.,
p. 143.
3Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1979), p. 162.
4Keith Lehrer, Theory of Knowledge (Boulder: Westview Press, 1990), p. 87.
5Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, p. 178.
5Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, p. 178.
REFERENCES
Carnap, Rudolf, The
Logical Structure of the World & Pseudoproblems in Philosophy (Der logische Aufbau der Welt, 1924),
translated by Rolf A. George
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1969).
Chisholm, Roderick. Theory
of Knowledge (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1966).
Descartes, René. “Meditations on First Philosophy” [1641], in Ten Great Works of Philosophy, edited by
Robert Paul Wolff (New York: Penguin Books, 1969).
Dretske, Fred. “Gettier and Justified True Belief: 50 Years On,” in TPM Online, Jan. 23, 2015, at http://www.philosophersmag.com/index.php/tpm-mag-articles/11-essays/10-gettier-and-justified-true-belief-50-years-on.
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. Science
of Knowledge (WIssenschaftlehre,
1794-95), edited and translated by Peter Heath (New York: Meredith Corporation,
1970).
Gettier, Edmund L. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” in Analysis, Vol. 23, No. 6 (June, 1963),
pp. 121-123.
Hume, David. A Treatise of Human
Nature [1739], edited by Ernest C. Mossner (London: Penguin Books, 1969).
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure
Reason (Kritik der reinen Vernunft,
1781), translated byJ.M.D.Meiklejohn (Amherst: Prometheus Books, 1990).
Lehrer, Keith. Theory
of Knowledge (Boulder: Westview Press, 1990).
Locke, John. An Essay Concerning
Human Understanding [1689], edited by Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1975).
Malachowski, Alan R. “Deep Epistemology without Foundations
(in Language),” in Reading Rorty:
Critical Responses to Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (and Beyond),
edited by Alan R. Malachowski (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, Ltd., 1990).
Plato. Theaetetus.
Translated by M.J. Levett. (Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company, 1992).
Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and
the Mirror of Nature. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979).
Russell, Bertrand. Theory of
Knowledge: The 1913 Manuscript, edited by Elizabeth Ramsden Eames in
collaboration with Kenneth Blackwell (London: George Allen & Unwin , 1984).
Schelling, F.W.J. System of
Transcendental Idealism (System des
transcendentalen Idealismus, 1800), translated by Peter Heath
(Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1978).
Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World
as Will and Representation (Die Welt
als Wille und Vorstellung, 1818), Vols. I and II, translated by E.F.J.
Payne (New York: Harper & Row, 1968).
Sosa, Ernest. Knowing Full Well
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2011).
Turri, John. “Manifest Failure: The Gettier Problem Solved,” in Philosophers’ Imprint, Vol. 11, No. 8,
April 2011, pp. 1-11.
Zagzebski, Linda. “The Inescapability of Gettier Problems,” in The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 44,
No. 174 (Jan., 1994), pp. 65-73.
No comments:
Post a Comment