I had the good fortune to be able to attend a philosophy conference at Johns Hopkins today, and to meet some distinguished philosophers. The conference was sponsored by the Department of Philosophy and the Center for Africana Studies. Below are some photos.
Saturday, April 8, 2017
Sunday, April 2, 2017
What is Lived Theology?
The term “lived theology” may be definable in so many ways
that no single definition may be adequate. Lived theology may be a
philosophical or practical theology. It may be a moral, ethical, pastoral, ecumenical,
or political theology, It may be a theological aesthetics or theological
hermeneutics. It may be a liberation theology, resistance theology, reconciliation theology, or some other kind of social theology.
Perhaps instead of trying to answer
the question, “What is lived theology?”, we each should try to answer the
question, “What does it mean to live my theology?” We each may need to ask
ourselves: Am I living my theology? Do my actions reflect my theology? Is my theology dying or dead, or is it a living thing? Do I believe in a
living God? How am I living my faith?
We may also have to distinguish
between theology as dogma or doctrine and theology as daily practice or social
action. We may at some point have to think about our own lives differently, and think
about theology differently. If we say that God is love, and that we believe in
a theology of love, then we each may have to ask ourselves: Am I trying to love
others in the same way that God loves each of us? Am I showing love and understanding toward others in the same way that God shows love and understanding toward each of us?
Lived theology is not something that
can be done merely individually; it must be done collectively. To really live
theology, we cannot merely act as individuals, we must live our theology as
members of a (spiritual, religious, vocational, or social) community.
Perhaps we should also distinguish
between “living theology” (or expressing in our daily lives what we believe
about God) and “living theologically” (or acting according to a rule
book or set of doctrines). The phrase “living theology” may also have different
meanings, depending on whether the emphasis is placed on the word “living” or
on the word “theology.” Living
theology places the emphasis on our daily actions and ongoing experiences, while
living theology places the emphasis
on our religious beliefs and convictions about the nature of God.
Carl R. Holladay, professor of New Testament studies at Emory University Candler School of Theology, explains that “living our theology…is inseparable from having and doing theology.” We cannot really have a theology without living and doing
that theology. When we do
theology, we are putting our faith into action. Lived theology is faith in
action.1
David Dark, professor of religion at Belmont University College of Theology, answers the question
“What is Lived Theology?” by saying, “One would think that the “lived” in
“lived theology” would in some sense be redundant. But we have our world so
divided up, and our God-talk so divided up from our actual lived commitments, that the term “lived theology” ends up being a very helpful provocation.”2
Charles Marsh,
professor of religious studies at the University of Virginia, explains that
lived theology as a subject of theological writing, research, and teaching examines
the impact of our daily experiences on our theological beliefs and
practices. Lived theology may be a unique way of understanding how we feel
God’s presence in our lives.3
Insofar as “living” means “living in a body,” “lived theology” means
theology lived in a body (or through the body as a medium of experience) or
embodied theology. The corporeality of lived theology anchors it in daily
experience. It cannot be merely a spiritual practice; it must also be social
and communal.
Insofar as theology is a mode of discourse
about God, the discursivity of lived theology may be expressed by our capacity to communicate (e.g. by speech or writing) through our daily actions our thoughts and feelings about
God.
FOOTNOTES
1Carl R. Holladay, A Critical Introduction to the New Testament: Interpreting the Message
and Meaning of Jesus Christ (Nashville: Abington Press, 2005), p. 10.
2David Dark, “What is Lived Theology?", The Project
on Lived Theology (Sept. 4, 2015), online at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=O3Fnf__Ea10.
3Charles Marsh, “Lived Theology: Method, Style,
and Pedagogy,” in Lived Theology: New
Perspectives on Method, Style, and Pedagogy, edited by Charles Marsh, Peter
Slade, and Sarah Azaransky (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), pp. 6-7.
Tuesday, March 14, 2017
Bonhoeffer's Ethics
Dietrich Bonhoeffer (1906-1945) was a German Lutheran pastor
and theologian who was active in the resistance movement against Nazism in
Germany during the 1930’s and 1940’s. He was imprisoned and eventually executed
in a concentration camp. He was a very heroic and inspiring figure of
self-sacrifice and moral commitment, and he became one of the most influential
Protestant theologians of the twentieth century.1
Bonhoeffer’s ethics are religious
and Christian ethics. They are also Christological and Christocentric ethics.
He says, “We began by saying that, instead of asking how one can be good and do
good, one must ask what is the will of God. But the will of God is nothing
other than the becoming real of the reality of Christ with us and in our world.
The will of God, therefore, is not an idea, still demanding to become real; it
is itself a reality already in the self-revelation of God in Jesus Christ.”2
The reality of Christ and the
reality of the world are one and the same, says Bonhoeffer. The world has no
reality of its own, beyond its reality as God’s revelation in Christ. The world
is only real insofar as God reveals Himself to us in it.3
Christian ethics can therefore have
only one purpose: participation in the reality of the fulfilled will of God. If
we are reconciled with God, then we will be included in the fulfillment of
God’s will in Christ.4
What then does Bonhoeffer have to
offer to those who are interested in a non-religious or secular ethics? Not
much. He seems to say that we must realize that our world is relative to
Christ, whether we want to admit it or not. “There can be no retreating from a
‘secular’ into a ‘spiritual’ sphere,” he says. “There can only be the practice,
the learning, of the Christian life under (the)…mandates of God.”5
He also says, “The world, like all created things, is created through Christ
and with Christ as its end, and consists in Christ alone (John 1:10; Col.
1:16). To speak of the world without speaking of Christ is empty and abstract.
The world is relative to Christ, no matter whether it knows it or not.”6
Bonhoeffer says that only if we
believe (in Christ) are we (or can we be) obedient (to the call to
discipleship, and to the call to life in the fellowship of Christ), and only if
we are obedient do we (or can we) believe. Faith makes obedience possible, but
faith is only real when there is obedience.7 Obedience is therefore
not merely a consequence of faith; it’s also a presupposition of faith. “Faith
is the condition of obedience,” and “obedience is the condition of faith.”8
Only the obedient believe, and only believers are obedient. Believers obey the
call to discipleship. The call to discipleship is a call to submission, a call
to take up the cross. If we take up the cross, then we prove that suffering
love can vanquish evil.9 Discipleship grants us participation in the
cross.
We’re justified by faith alone, but
we’re also justified by God’s grace alone. Faith is only possible with God’s
grace. But faith is never alone; it’s always accompanied by love and hope.10
What is love? The answer is clearly
“God is love” (1 John 4:16). But Bonhoeffer says that the emphasis should be
placed on the word “God,” even though we’ve fallen into the habit of emphasizing
the word “love.” God is love.11
Only by knowing God can we know love, rather than the other way around. To know
God is to know love, but we can only know God through God’s self-revelation.
Love is the (self-)revelation of God, and God’s (self-)revelation in Christ is
the revelation of His love for us. 12 Love is also our
reconciliation with God in (and through) Christ.13
Our moral responsibility for our
actions depends on our freedom to make responsible choices. Where there is no
freedom, there is no responsibility. Responsibility therefore presupposes
freedom, and freedom can only consist in responsibility.14 However,
obedience and responsibility are also interlinked in such a way that obedience
is rendered in responsibility.15 Obedience without freedom is
bondage, but freedom without obedience becomes arbitrary self-will.16
In responsibility, both freedom and obedience are realized.17
Christian ethics, according to
Bonhoeffer, are not a matter of our merely applying Christ’s teachings to the
world, but rather of our being shaped in the form, or conforming to the
likeness, of Christ. We are shaped in the form, or conform to the likeness, of
Christ not by our own efforts, but by Christ who shapes us in conformity with
Himself.18 Thus, we take the form that God has given us as members
of Christ’s body, the Church.19
Christian ethics are also based on
the unity of the incarnation, cross, and resurrection. Christian life,
according to Bonhoeffer, is “life with the incarnate, crucified, and risen
Christ, whose word confronts us…in the message of the justification of the
sinner by grace alone.”20 Christian life also means that we become
human through the efficacy of the incarnation, we are sentenced and pardoned
through the efficacy of the cross, and we lead new lives through the efficacy
of the resurrection.21 All three forms or efficacy are
interconnected and interdependent.
Regarding the right to life,
Bonhoeffer says that “In the sight of God, there is no life that is not worth
living: for life itself is valued by God.”22 Thus, he argues that
suicide and euthanasia are wrong, because “God maintains the right of life,”
even against those who have grown tired of living.23 Bonhoeffer sees
suicide as an attempt at self-justification, motivated by lack of faith in
divine justification. He says, “God has reserved to Himself the right to
determine the end of life, because He alone knows the goal to which it is His
will to lead it. It is for Him alone to justify a life or to cast it away.
Before God, self-justification is quite simply sin, and suicide is therefore
also sin.”24 Bonhoeffer also argues that contraception and abortion are
wrong, and that they violate the right to life. He also argues that
sterilization is wrong, unless it is performed for health reasons.
Regarding the relation between Church
and State, Bonhoeffer says that the State should be designed to serve God. “Jesus
submitted to government, but He reminded government that its power is not
arbitrary human will, but a ‘gift from above’ (John 19:10).”25
Government institutions should serve God by establishing and maintaining justice. Christians have
a duty to obey government, unless government forfeits its claim on them by
violating its mission to promote justice. The aim of the Church should be not
for the government to enact laws and pursue policies that favor Christians, but
for the government to fulfill its mission of justice.
FOOTNOTES
1Eric Pace, “Eberhard Bethge, 90, Theologian and
Biographer,” in The New York Times,
April 18, 2000, online at http://www.nytimes.com/2000/04/18/world/eberhard-bethge-90-writer-theologian-and-biographer.html.
2Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Ethics, translated by Neville Horton Smith from the German Ethik, Chr. Kaiser Verlag, Munich, 1949
(New York: Simon & Schuster, 1955), p. 77.
3Ibid.,
p. 195.
4Ibid.,
p. 209.
5Ibid.,
p. 204.
6Ibid.,
p. 204.
7Dietrich Bonhoeffer, The Cost of Discipleship, translated by R.H. Fuller, with some
revision by Irmgard Booth, from the German Nachfolge,
first published 1937 by Chr. Kaiser Verlag München (New York: The MacMillan Company,
1959), p. 54.
8Ibid., p. 54.
9Ibid., p. 130.
10Bonhoeffer, Ethics, p. 121.
11Ibid., p. 53.
12Ibid., p. 53.
13Ibid., p. 55.
14Ibid., p. 244.
15Ibid., p. 248.
16Ibid., p. 248.
17Ibid., p. 249.
18Ibid., p. 82.
19Ibid., p. 84.
20Ibid., p. 132.
21Ibid., p. 132.
22Ibid., p. 162.
23Ibid., p. 168.
24Ibid., p. 167.
25Ibid., p. 333.
Saturday, February 18, 2017
Why Rorty's Conception of Epistemology is Wrong
With the very first paragraph of Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979), Richard Rorty's conception of epistemology starts to go astray, as he begins his criticism of traditional
epistemology by saying that such philosophers as Descartes, Locke, Kant, Russell, and Husserl have sought to adjudicate claims to knowledge by trying to define the
“foundations” of knowledge. Rorty says that if knowledge is seen as being based
on accurate mental representations of the world, then the mind may be seen as a
mirror of nature, and philosophy’s task may be seen as that of adjudicating knowledge
claims by judging the accuracy of their representations of reality. He criticizes
this mentalist and representationalist approach to the theory of knowledge,
saying that epistemology as it has, in his view, traditionally been practiced
(as a theory of representation) should be abandoned.
Rorty conflates the search for the
“foundations” of knowledge with the search for the “conditions” of knowledge,
however. The distinction between the two is important, although he might
deny this and might say that the conditions of knowledge are merely
foundational principles of knowledge. There is a difference, however, between
seeking to establish certain basic or foundational truths and seeking to
establish the conditions under which those basic or foundational truths may be known.
While the “foundationalist” approach may seek to define certain basic truths or
knowledge claims on which other truths or knowledge claims can be based, the “conditionalist”
approach may seek to define the necessary and sufficient conditions under which truth or knowledge claims can be made. Rorty identifies epistemology with
foundationalism, and he therefore rejects it. But his critique of epistemology amounts
to a kind of straw man argument. He criticizes epistemology for being something
that it is not (al least not in the view of many classical and modern
philosophers).
This is not to say that epistemology
is merely an attempt to define the conditions of knowledge. It is much more
than that. It's also concerned with the nature, extent, and limits of human knowledge,
the formulation and communication of knowledge, and the differences between
knowledge and belief, opinion, faith, and imagination.
Alan Malachowsksi (1990) explains
that Rorty also tends to conflate the notion that it is unwise to crave for a
theory of knowledge with the notion that it is unwise to think of knowledge as
something that has or needs foundations, and that Rorty fails to establish the truth of either of these notions.1 Since
Rorty also claims that it’s unwise to pursue an epistemologically-centered philosophy,
Malachowski says that it’s fair to ask whether Rorty’s views actually amount to a
substantive position on epistemology, and that this may indeed be a difficult
question to answer.2
Descartes (1641) is a
foundationalist, insofar as he argues that we can know the truth of things if
we have clear and distinct ideas about them. He says there are
innate ideas in the human mind that are independent of our own perceptions and our
own will. All innate ideas are clear and distinct, but adventitious ideas
derived from our perceptions and factitious ideas derived from our illusions or
imaginations may be unclear and indistinct.
Locke (1689) is also a
foundationalist, insofar as he describes three “degrees” of knowledge:
intuitive, demonstrative, and sensory. According to Locke, intuitive knowledge
is an immediate perception of the agreement or disagreement of two or more
ideas, without the intervention of any other ideas. Demonstrative knowledge is
a perception of the agreement or disagreement or two or more ideas, based on
proofs provided by intervening ideas. Sensory knowledge is a perception of the
agreement or disagreement of two or more ideas, based on sensory experience of
the external objects to which those ideas refer. Demonstrative knowledge is
based on intuitive knowledge, and intuitive certainty is required for every
step of reasoning that produces demonstrative certainty. The faculty of
understanding is necessary, however, in order to combine the three degrees of
knowledge (intuition, demonstration, and sensation) into a more unified and
comprehensive knowledge that transcends the respective limits of reason, intuition, and
experience.
Hume (1739) is also a foundationalist, insofar as he says that all ideas are originally derived from sensory
perceptions, and that knowledge is ultimately based on experience rather than
reason. Hume says that in order to establish the existence of an object, we
must have already had a sensory perception of that object or of other objects
from which the existence of that object can be inferred. Reason alone is
insufficient to establish the existence of an object; sensory perception of
that object, directly or indirectly, is necessary.
Russell (1913) is also a
foundationalist, insofar as he says that knowledge is based on acquaintance
with self-evident truths. According to Russell, true propositions that are not
self-evident must, in order to become objects of knowledge, be demonstrated to
be true by self-evident propositions.. Knowledge is based on acquaintance with
self-evident propositions and with propositions whose truth can be demonstrated
by self-evident propositions.
Carnap (1924) is also a
foundationalist, insofar as he says that all scientific statements are
reducible to structural statements about basic elements of experience. According
to Carnap, structural statements are logical propositions about the formal
properties of objects or relations. A constructional system of reality is a
system in which the objects of each level are constructed from objects of more
elementary levels of construction. The most elementary level of a
constructional system is the level of basic objects, which includes basic
elements and basic relations. The basic elements of a constructional system are
“elementary experiences” that are not constructed but are immediately given to
consciousness as formal objects.
The “conditionalist” philosophers, on the other hand, may include Plato, Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Schopenhauer, and others.
For Plato, belief, truth, and
justification are conditions of knowledge. True beliefs constitute knowledge if
they can be logically justified. In response to the kinds of counterexamples
supplied by Edmund Gettier (1963) of cases in which justified true beliefs may
not constitute knowledge, many contemporary philosophers have proposed immunity to Gettier
cases as another condition of knowledge. This subject has been discussed by
such philosophers as Chisholm (1989), Lehrer (1990), Zagzebski (1994), Sosa (2011), Turri (2011), and Dretske (2015).
Kant (1781) may be both a
foundationalist, insofar as he calls for a critique of pure reason in order to
determine the possibility, principles and extent of a priori knowledge, and a conditionalist, insofar as he attempts to
describe the conditions under which a
priori knowledge is possible. He provides a table of twelve categories or pure
concepts of the understanding, describing them as a priori concepts that define conditions of possible experience.
These categories or pure concepts of the understanding also define conditions
under which the content of intuitions and representations may be unified by the
understanding.
Fichte (1794-95)
claims that the first, absolutely unconditioned principle of the science of
knowledge is the act by which the self becomes conscious of itself. The second
principle, conditioned as to content, is the act by which the non-self is
opposed to the self. The third principle, conditioned as to form, is the act by
which the self and non-self are posited as divisible so that a limited self may
be opposed to a limited non-self.
Schelling (1800)
argues that transcendental idealism is a system for all knowledge, and that it affirms
that a transcendental unity of the self and nature, the subjective and
objective, and the conscious and unconscious is a condition of knowledge.
Schopenhauer (1818) says that
transcendental idealism affirms that a transcendental unity of reason and
experience is the condition for knowledge. He also says that all knowledge,
except for knowledge of Platonic Ideas, depends on the principle of sufficient
reason, and that the conditions for knowledge of Platonic Ideas include pure
contemplation, extinction of desire, transcendence of the subject-object relation, and freedom from confinement by individuality.
Rorty describes epistemology as a
discipline concerned with the possibility of accurate representation, as if
most epistemologists have already agreed that this is what epistemology is, and as if
this is all it can be. In his view, if knowledge is not a matter of accurate
representation, then we have no more need of epistemology. But this is a very skeptical and simple-minded view of epistemology. Does Rorty actually
believe that a theory of accurate representation is all that epistemology can
be? Is he perhaps being intentionally obtuse and simplistic for the sake of
provoking some sort of critical response?
His position also seems
to be that to debunk Cartesian mind-body dualism is to debunk epistemology.
He criticizes the concept of
philosophy as a foundational discipline for other disciplines, as a discipline
that can adjudicate the procedures and truth claims of other disciplines. He also
criticizes the concept of philosophy as a discipline that “takes as its study
the ‘formal’ or ‘structural’ aspects of our beliefs,” serving “the cultural
function of keeping other disciplines honest” by “limiting their claims to what
can be properly ‘grounded.’”3
There may, however, exist within
epistemology viable alternatives to foundationalism, which Rorty doesn't seem
to account for. For example, Keith Lehrer (1990) explains that the explanatory
coherence theory of justification (that justification is a reciprocal relation
of coherence among beliefs belonging to a system) may be an alternative to the
foundation theory (that some beliefs are completely justified in themselves and
can therefore serve as the foundation for the justification of other beliefs).4 Rorty comes close to acknowledging this when he says, "For the Quine-Sellars approach to epistemology, to say that truth and knowledge can only be judged by the standards of the inquirers of our own day is not to say that human knowledge is less noble or important...than we had thought. It is merely to say that nothing counts as justification unless by reference to what we already accept, and that there is no way to get outside of our own beliefs and our language so as to find some test other than coherence."5
Infinitism (the theory that beliefs may be justified for an infinite number of reasons) may be another alternative to the foundation theory.
Infinitism (the theory that beliefs may be justified for an infinite number of reasons) may be another alternative to the foundation theory.
FOOTNOTES
1Alan R. Malachowski, “Deep Epistemology without
Foundations (in Language),” in Reading
Rorty: Critical Responses to Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (and Beyond),
edited by Alan R. Malachowski (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, Ltd., 1990), pp.
140-141.
2Ibid.,
p. 143.
3Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1979), p. 162.
4Keith Lehrer, Theory of Knowledge (Boulder: Westview Press, 1990), p. 87.
5Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, p. 178.
5Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, p. 178.
REFERENCES
Carnap, Rudolf, The
Logical Structure of the World & Pseudoproblems in Philosophy (Der logische Aufbau der Welt, 1924),
translated by Rolf A. George
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1969).
Chisholm, Roderick. Theory
of Knowledge (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1966).
Descartes, René. “Meditations on First Philosophy” [1641], in Ten Great Works of Philosophy, edited by
Robert Paul Wolff (New York: Penguin Books, 1969).
Dretske, Fred. “Gettier and Justified True Belief: 50 Years On,” in TPM Online, Jan. 23, 2015, at http://www.philosophersmag.com/index.php/tpm-mag-articles/11-essays/10-gettier-and-justified-true-belief-50-years-on.
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. Science
of Knowledge (WIssenschaftlehre,
1794-95), edited and translated by Peter Heath (New York: Meredith Corporation,
1970).
Gettier, Edmund L. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” in Analysis, Vol. 23, No. 6 (June, 1963),
pp. 121-123.
Hume, David. A Treatise of Human
Nature [1739], edited by Ernest C. Mossner (London: Penguin Books, 1969).
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure
Reason (Kritik der reinen Vernunft,
1781), translated byJ.M.D.Meiklejohn (Amherst: Prometheus Books, 1990).
Lehrer, Keith. Theory
of Knowledge (Boulder: Westview Press, 1990).
Locke, John. An Essay Concerning
Human Understanding [1689], edited by Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1975).
Malachowski, Alan R. “Deep Epistemology without Foundations
(in Language),” in Reading Rorty:
Critical Responses to Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (and Beyond),
edited by Alan R. Malachowski (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, Ltd., 1990).
Plato. Theaetetus.
Translated by M.J. Levett. (Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company, 1992).
Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and
the Mirror of Nature. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979).
Russell, Bertrand. Theory of
Knowledge: The 1913 Manuscript, edited by Elizabeth Ramsden Eames in
collaboration with Kenneth Blackwell (London: George Allen & Unwin , 1984).
Schelling, F.W.J. System of
Transcendental Idealism (System des
transcendentalen Idealismus, 1800), translated by Peter Heath
(Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1978).
Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World
as Will and Representation (Die Welt
als Wille und Vorstellung, 1818), Vols. I and II, translated by E.F.J.
Payne (New York: Harper & Row, 1968).
Sosa, Ernest. Knowing Full Well
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2011).
Turri, John. “Manifest Failure: The Gettier Problem Solved,” in Philosophers’ Imprint, Vol. 11, No. 8,
April 2011, pp. 1-11.
Zagzebski, Linda. “The Inescapability of Gettier Problems,” in The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 44,
No. 174 (Jan., 1994), pp. 65-73.
Sunday, February 5, 2017
The Obligatoriness of Washing Our Hands, and the Permissibility of Getting Them Dirty
Consider all the possible statements we could make about whether we should wash our hands, and what they reveal about the kinds of (personal, moral, and social) decisions we could make. Some examples are:
We should (must, or have to) wash our hands now.
We shouldn’t (mustn’t, or don’t have to) wash our hands now.
We would (probably, likely, or most certainly) be remiss if we weren’t to go ahead and wash our hands now.
We don’t have to wash our hands now, unless we won’t have time to wash them later.
It’s probably best that we wash our hands now, rather than later.
If our hands aren’t dirty, then we don’t have to wash them now.
If our hands are dirty, then we should wash them now, rather than later.
It would be better to wash our hands now, because someone might notice that they're dirty.
It doesn’t matter whether we wash our hands right now or sometime later. In fact, it doesn’t (or may not) matter whether we wash them at all.
We don’t have to wash our hands now, unless there is someone we know who thinks we should.
We'd better wash our hands now, because we don’t want people to think we’re being careless about making sure our hands are clean before we shake their hands.
We could wash our hands right now, but we don’t really have to, so we might as well wait until later.
We might as well wash our hands right now.
Washing our hands right now is no better than washing them later.
If there are sanitary facilities available, then we should go ahead and wash our hands now.
If there is hand sanitizer available (and if our hands aren’t too dirty), then we can use the sanitizer instead of washing our hands with soap and water.
If we’ve touched something unclean or dirty, then we should wash our hands with soap and water as soon as we can.
If we’ve already washed our hands, then we don’t need to wash them again right now, unless there is some reason for us to get them extra clean.
If it’s more likely that we’ll have time to wash our hands now than later, then we should go ahead and wash them now.
If we wash our hands now, then we can still (or might still be able to) wash them later.
If we wash our hands now, then we won’t have to wash them again later.
Most of these statements are modal expressions employing modal auxiliary verbs such as “may,” “might,” “will,” won’t,” “can,” “could,” “should,” and “must” to indicate deontic modality (moral possibility or necessity). They vary in the strength of moral necessity that they express, with some expressing only moral possibility or permissibility, and others expressing moral necessity or obligatoriness.
Given all the possible decisions we can or could make (and all the possible ways of rationalizing those decisions) regarding whether it is or isn't permissible, advisable, or necessary to wash our hands at a given moment, how are we able to decide what to do without consciously thinking about it? Such a decision-making process seems in most cases to be an unconscious and effortless one (unless for some reason, such as a mental or behavioral disorder, we have an obsessive or compulsive habit of washing our hands).
In daily life, why is it that we don’t ever (or so rarely) seem to have any difficulty deciding whether to wash our hands? Is it because we’re always so busy doing something else that deciding whether to wash our hands at a given moment becomes very easy whenever the opportunity presents itself?
According to CDC guidelines, we should wash our hands before, during, and after preparing food; before eating food; before and after caring for someone who is sick; before and after treating a cut or wound; after using the toilet; after changing diapers or cleaning up a child who has used the toilet; after blowing our noses, coughing, or sneezing; after touching an animal, animal feed, or animal waste; after handling pet food or pet treats; and after touching garbage.1
Metaphorically speaking, when are we morally obligated to wash our hands of something, and when are we morally obligated to risk getting our hands dirty? When should we accept moral uncertainty in a given situation rather than refuse to risk any compromise of our moral principles? Risking moral blame or culpability may actually in some cases require a greater degree of moral commitment than refusing to put our own personal reputations at risk. We may in some cases have to risk getting our hands dirty if we've put ourselves in a position of responsibility that requires us to compromise our moral principles for the sake of a greater good (unless we've consciously or unconsciously avoided putting ourselves in that position to begin with).
An example of a “dirty hands” problem might be the president or prime minister who orders drone strikes against known terrorists, targeting them for destruction but thereby potentially endangering the lives of innocent civilians. However, Ben Jones and John M. Parrish (2016) argue that the dirty hands problem “describes an emergency that forces an individual to break a moral rule, not a policy that routinely breaks moral rules.” They also argue that “Rather than provide moral clarity, dirty hands justifications of current U.S. drone policy risk legitimizing a practice that expands state power in potentially dangerous ways.”2
Michael Walzer (1973) argues that the politician who has dirty hands, even if he has acted out of concern for the common good, must nevertheless bear a burden of guilt and responsibility for his blameworthy actions. It is in fact by the politician’s acceptance of guilt and responsibility (why guilt, necessarily?) for his blameworthy actions that we know him to be a moral person. If he were not a moral person, then he would pretend that his hands were clean.3 Once he has atoned for his wrongdoing, then his hands will be clean again.
Stephen de Wijze (2007) argues that the dirty hands problem may be a case of “doing right by doing wrong” or “doing wrong to do right,” but may also be subject to various conceptual confusions. He explains that it may involve either a moral conflict in which a right choice can be made between incompossible duties or a moral dilemma in which there is no right overall choice between incompossible duties (and in which there may only be a choice between the lesser of two evils). Some dirty hands problems may involve moral conflicts but not dilemmas, while others may involve both moral conflicts and dilemmas. De Witze also argues, following Michael Stocker (1990), that a dirty hands problem is a special kind of moral conflict in which an action is ‘justified, even obligatory, but also none the less somehow wrong.’4 However, de Witze explains that “not every wrong action is a dirty action and not every moral conflict involves dirty hands. Furthermore, there can be dirty hands cases which involve moral dilemmas, whereas many moral dilemma situations do not involve dirty hands.”5
Steve Buckler (1993) describes the dirty hands problem as an example of moral ambiguity in which there may be a choice between what is morally necessary and what is morally good. Some actions, despite being morally necessary, are in themselves not morally good. Thus, dirty hands cases may not be true dilemmas, which require a choice between two or more undesirable alternatives. The politician or government official, for example, may get dirty hands simply by doing what it's morally necessary for her to do (in order to promote the common good), rather than doing what it would be morally good for her to do. She may do exactly what she has to do, even though it may be morally disagreeable. In fact, this may be an obligation for her as a politician or government official, and failure to perform the necessary but morally disagreeable action may represent a neglect of her duty to the people she represents.6
FOOTNOTES
1Center for Disease Control and Prevention, “Handwashing: Clean Hands Save Lives,” September 4, 2015, online at https://www.cdc.gov/handwashing/when-how-handwashing.html.
2Ben Jones and John M. Parrish, “Drones and Dirty Hands,” in Preventive Force: Drones, Targeted Killing, and the Transformation of Contemporary Warfare, edited by Kerstin Fisk
3Michael Walzer, “Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands,” in Philosophy and Public Affairs, Volume 2, Issue 2 (Winter, 1973), p. 168.
4Michael Stocker, “Dirty Hands and Ordinary Life,” in Plural and Conflicting Values (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 9-36.
5Stephen de Wijze, “Dirty hands: Doing Wrong to do Right,” in Politics and Morality, edited by Igor Primoratz (New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2007), p. 9.
6Steve Buckler, Dirty Hands: The Problem of Political Morality (Avebury: Ashgate Publishing Limited, 1993), p. 7.
6Steve Buckler, Dirty Hands: The Problem of Political Morality (Avebury: Ashgate Publishing Limited, 1993), p. 7.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)