anti-eliminativism - 1. the theory that the concept of race should not be eliminated from our thinking about personal or social identity, or from our discourse, social policy, public documents, etc. It may be expressed as conservationism (retentionism) or reconstructionism.
anti-objectivism - 1. the theory that race is not an objective biological or social category. Anti-objectivist positions include subjectivism (the theory that all racial categories are subjectively, rather than objectively defined) and relativism (the theory that all racial categories are relative to a particular society, culture, or time in history).
anti-realism - 1. the theory that race is not a real biological or social category.
conservationism (retentionism or preservationism) - 1. the theory that the concept of race should be conserved (retained or preserved), rather than eliminated.
deflationary realism - 1. a minimalist, social constructivist, nonracialist theory of race, according to which race is seen as a real social, but not fundamentally biological category.1
eliminativism - 1. the theory that the concept of race is false and misleading, and that it should be eliminated from our thinking about personal and social identity, as well as from our discourse, social policy, public documents, etc.
essentialism - 1. the theory that racial categories are defined by certain essential (physical, behavioral, and sociocultural) features, and that all members of a particular category possess those defining features.
geographical minimalism - 1. the theory that races are defined by various physical characteristics that correspond merely to differences in geographical ancestry.
objectivism - 1. the theory that race is an objective biological or social category. 2. the theory or assumption that race can be objectively determined or evaluated.
populationism - 1. as defined by Michael O. Hardimon (2017), "a nonracialist (nonessentialist, nonhierarchical) candidate scientific concept that characterizes races as groups of populations belonging to biological lines of descent, distinguished by patterns of phenotypic differences, that trace back to geographically separated and extrinsically reproductively isolated founding populations.”2
racialism - 1. the theory that races have essential characteristics, that they are distinguished by certain biological and social differences, and that they're also defined by ancestry and geographical origins. 2. the racist theory that races are distinguished by different physical and mental capabilities, different sets of skills and levels of intelligence, and different social and cultural behaviors, according to which they may be regarded as superior or inferior. Racialism may thus be closely associated with racism.3
realism - 1. the theory that race is a real biological or social category. Realist positions include conservationism and retentionism. However, social realism (the theory that race is a real social category) doesn't necessarily entail biological realism (the theory that race is a real biological category). Indeed, social realism may be associated with biological anti-realism (the theory that race is not a real biological category).
reconstructionism - 1. as defined by Joshua Glasgow (2009), is a substitutionist rather than eliminativist mode of discourse, in which the term "race" refers only to a social, and not to any biological category.4
social constructionism (or constructivism) - 1. the theory that racial categories are socially constructed. Albert Atkin (2012) distinguishes between strong and weak constructionism: while strong constructionism sees race as a real social category, weak constructionism may not see the sociocultural and sociohistorical impact of race as conferring upon it any basic underlying reality. Weak constructionism may thus be skeptical about the basic reality of race.5
FOOTNOTES
1Michael O. Hardimon, Rethinking Race: The Case for Deflationary Realism (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2017), p. 95.
2Ibid., p. 3.
3Ibid., p. 17.
4Joshua Glasgow, A Theory of Race (New York: Routledge, 2009), p. 139.
5Albert Atkin, The Philosophy of Race (Durham: Acumen, 2012), pp. 64-71.
OTHER SOURCES
Charles W. Mills, Blackness Visible: Essays on Philosophy and Race (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1998).
Jeremy Pierce, A Realist Metaphysics of Race: A Context-Sensitive, Short-Term Retentionist, Long-Term Revisionist Approach (Lanham: Lexington Books, 2015).
Friday, February 8, 2019
Monday, December 24, 2018
Treating Patients who have Substance Abuse Disorders and Chronic Pain
As a primary care physician, I see many patients who complain of chronic pain and who want me to prescribe pain medication. Many of these patients also have a history of substance abuse, however, and when I test them for active substance abuse by obtaining urine drug screens, the urine screens often come back positive for cocaine, methadone, fentanyl, marijuana, benzodiazepines, and other street drugs. So I must tell these patients I can't prescribe any opioid medication for their pain, because they're taking street drugs and need to stop taking dangerous, habit-forming drugs.
Although my initial impulse may sometimes be to feel a little angry or disappointed that patients have tried to deceive me by lying to me about their substance abuse or by asking me for prescriptions for opioids when they knew they already had opioids and other illicit substances in their bloodstream, I think that denial, dissemblance, and concealment of active substance abuse may also be part of the substance abuse disorders that many patients suffer from.
I don't think the most caring or tactful way to tell patients I can't prescribe opioids for their pain is to say bluntly, "I can't prescribe opioids for you, because you're a substance abuser." This kind of response is likely to anger them, and seems rather callous, uncaring, and condescending.
Some of the possible reasons why people might not want to be seen or described as substance abusers are that
(1) It may hurt their sense of pride.
(2) It may violate their sense of selfhood and individuality (they may feel they're being seen as just like everyone else who takes street drugs, and that everyone who takes street drugs is being seen as the same by the person who describes them as a substance abuser).
(3) It may make them feel that the person who sees them as a substance abuser feels that he or she is better than them, and that they are being seen as somehow less worthy of respect (it may make them feel marginalized and disrespected, and it may violate their sense of equal worth and personal dignity).
(4) They may in fact be in a state of denial that they are habitual substance abusers, and that their habit is in some ways dysfunctional.
(5) They may be wary of losing various legal and welfare rights to which they are entitled and which they may be in danger of being denied if they're seen merely as substance abusers.
(6) They may resent being labeled or dismissed as something they don't see themselves as (they may resent being assigned the label of "substance abuser" without their consent).
(7) It may make them feel they're being stereotyped, and that the uniqueness of their own life story, personal history, and social situation is being denied.
(8) It may make them feel they're being told that whatever distress of misfortune they're suffering from is their own fault (they may feel that being told they're substance abusers is an example of "blaming the victim").
(9) It may seem like an attempt to make them feel guilty about something they may or may not feel guilty about.
(10) It may seem like an intrusion on their personal or social space (they may not welcome a wake-up call about their substance abuse disorder).
(11) They may feel they're simply "self-medicating" (a term I think is often mistaken and misplaced. For someone to say "I was self-medicating" may often be a convenient way for them to try to disregard, deny, or justify their substance abuse disorder).
So physicians must respond compassionately to patients who suffer from substance abuse and chronic pain, not by allowing themselves to be misled into prescribing drugs that such patients will abuse, and not by treating such patients as if they were any less worthy of respect than other patients, but by approaching them as individuals and developing treatment plans with them that will recognize and respond to their personal health care needs.
The Maryland Board of Physicians guidelines for opioid prescribing include that before opioid prescribing, physicians should consider non-opioid therapies. Physicians should evaluate and inform patients of the risks and benefits of opioid use. They should establish a treatment plan and only continue prescribing opioids if the pain and functionality improvement outweigh the risks. They should screen for substance use disorders. They should consider red flags regarding potential abuse, misuse, and diversion of opioids. They should check the Prescription Drug Monitoring Program (PDMP) to review patient medical history of Controlled Dangerous Substances prescriptions. They should perform patient urine screening to confirm presence of prescribed medication and for undisclosed prescription drug or illicit substance use. And they should schedule a patient follow-up appointment 1-4 weeks after initial prescribing.1
The Maryland guidelines also include, regarding dosages and duration of opioids, that physicians should start low and go slow by prescribing the lowest effective dosages for the shortest possible duration. Physicians should avoid prescribing opioids and benzodiazepines concurrently. They should calculate the morphine milligram equivalent (MME) dosages, and if prescribing > 50 MME per day should increase appointment follow-up frequency and offer naloxone for overdose risk, should avoid prescribing > 90 MME per day if possible, carefully consider and justify such doses, and consider referring patients to a pain management specialist.2
The Maryland guidelines also include, regarding continued treatment with opioids, that physicians should reassess treatment goals and determine if opioids continue to be the best option. Physicians should reassess no less frequently than every three months. They should consider whether there are clinically meaningful improvements in pain and function that outweigh the risks or harms of opioid prescribing. They should consider whether any new red flags of substance abuse disorder or diversion are present. They should perform periodic urine toxicology screenings. If over-sedation or increased overdose risk is present, they should taper opioid prescribing while considering patient psychosocial support. If tapering opioids, they should monitor for withdrawal symptoms.3
The Maryland guidelines also include that for patients with substance abuse disorders, physicians should refer them for substance abuse treatment, should consider referring them to a pain management specialist, should consider medication-assisted treatment (MAT) such as buprenorphine, methadone, and naltrexone in combination with behavioral therapies, and should consider offering naloxone for those patients with high risk of overdose.4
A complete statement of the Maryland Board of Physicians guidelines can be found at the Maryland.gov website.
FOOTNOTES
1Maryland.gov Maryland Board of Physicians, "Board Guidance," at https://www.mbp.state.md.us/resource_information/res_con/resource_consumer_od_board_guidance.aspx
2Ibid.
3Ibid.
4Ibid.
Although my initial impulse may sometimes be to feel a little angry or disappointed that patients have tried to deceive me by lying to me about their substance abuse or by asking me for prescriptions for opioids when they knew they already had opioids and other illicit substances in their bloodstream, I think that denial, dissemblance, and concealment of active substance abuse may also be part of the substance abuse disorders that many patients suffer from.
I don't think the most caring or tactful way to tell patients I can't prescribe opioids for their pain is to say bluntly, "I can't prescribe opioids for you, because you're a substance abuser." This kind of response is likely to anger them, and seems rather callous, uncaring, and condescending.
Some of the possible reasons why people might not want to be seen or described as substance abusers are that
(1) It may hurt their sense of pride.
(2) It may violate their sense of selfhood and individuality (they may feel they're being seen as just like everyone else who takes street drugs, and that everyone who takes street drugs is being seen as the same by the person who describes them as a substance abuser).
(3) It may make them feel that the person who sees them as a substance abuser feels that he or she is better than them, and that they are being seen as somehow less worthy of respect (it may make them feel marginalized and disrespected, and it may violate their sense of equal worth and personal dignity).
(4) They may in fact be in a state of denial that they are habitual substance abusers, and that their habit is in some ways dysfunctional.
(5) They may be wary of losing various legal and welfare rights to which they are entitled and which they may be in danger of being denied if they're seen merely as substance abusers.
(6) They may resent being labeled or dismissed as something they don't see themselves as (they may resent being assigned the label of "substance abuser" without their consent).
(7) It may make them feel they're being stereotyped, and that the uniqueness of their own life story, personal history, and social situation is being denied.
(8) It may make them feel they're being told that whatever distress of misfortune they're suffering from is their own fault (they may feel that being told they're substance abusers is an example of "blaming the victim").
(9) It may seem like an attempt to make them feel guilty about something they may or may not feel guilty about.
(10) It may seem like an intrusion on their personal or social space (they may not welcome a wake-up call about their substance abuse disorder).
(11) They may feel they're simply "self-medicating" (a term I think is often mistaken and misplaced. For someone to say "I was self-medicating" may often be a convenient way for them to try to disregard, deny, or justify their substance abuse disorder).
So physicians must respond compassionately to patients who suffer from substance abuse and chronic pain, not by allowing themselves to be misled into prescribing drugs that such patients will abuse, and not by treating such patients as if they were any less worthy of respect than other patients, but by approaching them as individuals and developing treatment plans with them that will recognize and respond to their personal health care needs.
The Maryland Board of Physicians guidelines for opioid prescribing include that before opioid prescribing, physicians should consider non-opioid therapies. Physicians should evaluate and inform patients of the risks and benefits of opioid use. They should establish a treatment plan and only continue prescribing opioids if the pain and functionality improvement outweigh the risks. They should screen for substance use disorders. They should consider red flags regarding potential abuse, misuse, and diversion of opioids. They should check the Prescription Drug Monitoring Program (PDMP) to review patient medical history of Controlled Dangerous Substances prescriptions. They should perform patient urine screening to confirm presence of prescribed medication and for undisclosed prescription drug or illicit substance use. And they should schedule a patient follow-up appointment 1-4 weeks after initial prescribing.1
The Maryland guidelines also include, regarding dosages and duration of opioids, that physicians should start low and go slow by prescribing the lowest effective dosages for the shortest possible duration. Physicians should avoid prescribing opioids and benzodiazepines concurrently. They should calculate the morphine milligram equivalent (MME) dosages, and if prescribing > 50 MME per day should increase appointment follow-up frequency and offer naloxone for overdose risk, should avoid prescribing > 90 MME per day if possible, carefully consider and justify such doses, and consider referring patients to a pain management specialist.2
The Maryland guidelines also include, regarding continued treatment with opioids, that physicians should reassess treatment goals and determine if opioids continue to be the best option. Physicians should reassess no less frequently than every three months. They should consider whether there are clinically meaningful improvements in pain and function that outweigh the risks or harms of opioid prescribing. They should consider whether any new red flags of substance abuse disorder or diversion are present. They should perform periodic urine toxicology screenings. If over-sedation or increased overdose risk is present, they should taper opioid prescribing while considering patient psychosocial support. If tapering opioids, they should monitor for withdrawal symptoms.3
The Maryland guidelines also include that for patients with substance abuse disorders, physicians should refer them for substance abuse treatment, should consider referring them to a pain management specialist, should consider medication-assisted treatment (MAT) such as buprenorphine, methadone, and naltrexone in combination with behavioral therapies, and should consider offering naloxone for those patients with high risk of overdose.4
A complete statement of the Maryland Board of Physicians guidelines can be found at the Maryland.gov website.
FOOTNOTES
1Maryland.gov Maryland Board of Physicians, "Board Guidance," at https://www.mbp.state.md.us/resource_information/res_con/resource_consumer_od_board_guidance.aspx
2Ibid.
3Ibid.
4Ibid.
Wednesday, December 12, 2018
Linda Zagzebski's Exemplarist Moral Theory
Linda Zagzebski’s Exemplarist Moral Theory (2017) is a very cogent and persuasive attempt to construct a comprehensive moral theory by directly referring to moral exemplars, of whom she identifies three types: heroes, saints, and sages. Moral exemplars, according to Zagzebski, are people we regard as admirable and may therefore attempt to emulate, because they embody moral virtues, such as love, compassion, wisdom, and courage. Exemplars of non-moral qualities, such as athletically gifted or artistically talented persons, may also be admirable, but they may not be imitable in the same way or to the same extent that we can imitate moral exemplars, unless they have developed their gifts or talents through other qualities that we can imitate, such as determination and hard work.
Zagzebski observes that we may sometimes be mistaken in our admiration of people, and we may sometimes envy or resent, rather than admire people for their admirable qualities. We may also disagree about what exactly we admire in some person(s). However, an advantage of exemplarist moral theory is that we may often be more certain that some people, like Confucius, the Dalai Lama, and the Buddha are admirable than we are of what exactly is admirable about them.1
Zagzebski also notes that we may not always be able to fully imitate the admirable qualities of moral exemplars, unless we completely refocus our lives, which may be very difficult for many of us. Even though such saintly figures as St. Francis of Assisi, St Catherine of Siena, and Mother Theresa may be very admirable for their self-sacrifice and love for strangers, we may not have the moral resources to be able to emulate them in every respect. We may also not always regard moral saintliness as something desirable or something we want to completely devote ourselves to trying to emulate. We may admire some things (such as lives of asceticism and self-sacrifice) without truly desiring them, and we may desire some things (such as lives of comfort and financial security) without truly admiring them.
Another point Zagzebski makes is that although the emotion of admiration is assigned a primary function in her moral theory, this fact in no way implies that admiration is necessarily a more trustworthy emotion than other emotions or that we should not attend to moral judgments justified by other emotions.2 Admiration shares with other emotions the features of (1) having an intentional object, (2) having an affective component, and (3) having a potentially motivating aspect. However, there may be at least two kinds of admiration: admiration for inborn talent, and admiration for acquired excellence. The latter kind is the more important one for exemplarist theory.
Three possible responses to an admirable person may be (1) to feel positively about her, leading to a desire to emulate her, (2) to feel negatively about, or benignly envious of her, but still leading to a desire to emulate her, and (3) to feel negatively about, or malignantly envious toward her, leading to a desire to deprive her of her admirable qualities.3 The third kind of response (malignant or spiteful envy) may arise from a kind of resentment, in which the envious person sees her own lack of, or inability to acquire, the admired good, and thus tries to deprive the admired person of that good, rather than try to acquire it herself.4
We may admire some people more than others if they are more consistently admirable or seem to have a deeper disposition to be admirable in a wider range of situations. We may also admire some people more than others if they are admirable in a greater variety of respects (for example, if they are tactful as well as honest, temperate as well as courageous). Moral examplars, according to Zagzebski, tend to be admirable in all or most of their acquired traits, although they don’t have be admirable to the highest degree in all their acquired traits (such a feat would be very difficult or impossible).
Zagzebski identifies Leopold Socha (1909-1946), a Polish sewage inspector who at great personal risk sheltered Jews from the Nazis during World War II, as an example of a hero. She identifies Jean Vanier (1928- ), a Canadian philosopher and theologian who founded L’Arche, an international federation of communities for the care of the mentally disabled, as an example of a saint. And she identifies Confucius (551-479 BCE) as an example of a sage.
Some of the distinctive qualities possessed by sages include wisdom, insight, understanding, reflectiveness, equanimity, open-mindedness, intellectual humility, fairness, self-discipline, and creativity in problem-solving.5
Among the advantages of exemplarist moral theory, according to Zagzebski, are that it may serve as a map, rather than a supposed manual for moral decision-making.
Among the purposes of such a theory are (1) to create a comprehensive ethical theory that serves the same purposes as deontological, consequentialist, and virtue theories, (2) to have practical application by structuring moral theory around a motivating emotion—the emotion of admiration, (3) to explain and justify a genealogy of morals, and to track moral development, (4) to link theoretical ethics with empirical research in psychology and neuroscience, and (5) to meet the needs of different communities, and to frame the discussion of moral theory in cross-cultural discourse, by allowing different communities to identify distinct but overlapping sets of moral exemplars.6
FOOTNOTES
1Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski, Exemplarist Moral Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), p. 10.
FOOTNOTES
1Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski, Exemplarist Moral Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), p. 10.
2Ibid., p. 28.
3Ibid., p. 53.
4Ibid., pp. 55-56.
5Ibid., p. 95.
6Ibid., pp. 3-4.
Saturday, November 17, 2018
Some Equivalence Relations in Hegel's Phenomenology that may Provide a Key to its Understanding
Spirit = Reality (spirit is reality, and reality is spirit)
Reason = (all) Reality [reason is (all) reality, and (all) reality is reason]
Reason = the conscious certainty of being all reality1 (or the certainty of consciousness that it is all reality2)
Reason = Self-consciousness4 (which exists both in itself and for itself, because the self as an object of self-consciousness is both an object in itself and for itself)
Independent self-consciousness = self-consciousness that is purely for itself and not for another (not determined by another)
Dependent self-consciousness = self-consciousness that is determined by another
The relation between independent and dependent self-consciousness = in a metaphorical sense, the relation between lordship and bondage or between master and slave
The “unhappy consciousness” = divided self-consciousness = the consciousness that is conscious of itself as divided and unable to reconcile itself with another
Consciousness (including self-consciousness) = the simple substance of Spirit
Self-consciousness as reason = all reality
Idealism = the Notion that reason is the conscious certainty of being all reality
Consciousness, insofar as it has Reason = Spirit5 = Reality6
The moments (or stages) of consciousness = sense-certainty, perception, and understanding
Pure being = the essence of sense-certainty7
The entire system of consciousness = the entire realm of the truth of Spirit8
Spirit in its truth = the living ethical world9 = the individual form of Spirit that proceeds from and returns to the self of Spirit10
Spirit = Reason = concrete ethical actuality
Natural Religion = Religion in which Spirit knows itself as its object in a “natural” or immediate shape12
Religion in the form of art = Religion in which the shape that Spirit takes is a form of self through the creative activity of consciousness13
Revealed Religion = Religion in which Spirit is presented in and for itself as a unity of its actual shape and true form of self14
Absolute being = the self-consciousness of Spirit15
Spirit as absolute being, which knows itself as all reality = all truth
Essence = that which has being in itself16 = the spiritual alone = the actual
The true alone = the actual
Spirit = self-supporting, absolute, real being17
Absolute Being = Spirit that is in-and-for-itself, insofar as it is simple eternal substance18
Science = the Spirit that knows itself as Spirit19
The way to science = the science of the experience of consciousness20
The description of the coming-to-be of Science as such = the phenomenology of Spirit21
(See also my review of the Phenomenology here.)
FOOTNOTES
1Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A.V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 142.
2Ibid., p. 140.
3Ibid., p. 263.
4Ibid., p. 139.
5Ibid., p. 265.
6Ibid., p. 217.
7Ibid., p. 59.
8Ibid., p. 56.
9Ibid., p. 265.
10Ibid., p. 265.
11Ibid., p. 410.
12Ibid., p. 416
13Ibid., p. 416.
14Ibid., p. 416.
15Ibid., p. 410.
16Ibid., p. 14.
17Ibid., p. 264.
18Ibid., p. 325.
19Ibid., p. 12.
20Ibid., p. 56.
21Ibid., p. 15.
Reason = (all) Reality [reason is (all) reality, and (all) reality is reason]
Reason = the conscious certainty of being all reality1 (or the certainty of consciousness that it is all reality2)
Reason = Spirit that knows itself in its truth, as the conscious certainty of being all reality3
Reason = Self-consciousness4 (which exists both in itself and for itself, because the self as an object of self-consciousness is both an object in itself and for itself)
Independent self-consciousness = self-consciousness that is purely for itself and not for another (not determined by another)
Dependent self-consciousness = self-consciousness that is determined by another
The relation between independent and dependent self-consciousness = in a metaphorical sense, the relation between lordship and bondage or between master and slave
The “unhappy consciousness” = divided self-consciousness = the consciousness that is conscious of itself as divided and unable to reconcile itself with another
Consciousness (including self-consciousness) = the simple substance of Spirit
Self-consciousness as reason = all reality
Idealism = the Notion that reason is the conscious certainty of being all reality
Consciousness, insofar as it has Reason = Spirit5 = Reality6
The moments (or stages) of consciousness = sense-certainty, perception, and understanding
Pure being = the essence of sense-certainty7
The entire system of consciousness = the entire realm of the truth of Spirit8
Spirit in its truth = the living ethical world9 = the individual form of Spirit that proceeds from and returns to the self of Spirit10
Spirit = Reason = concrete ethical actuality
Religion = the consciousness of absolute being11 = the fulfillment of the life of Spirit
The Three Forms of Religion = Natural Religion, Religion in the Form of Art, and Revealed Religion
Natural Religion = Religion in which Spirit knows itself as its object in a “natural” or immediate shape12
Religion in the form of art = Religion in which the shape that Spirit takes is a form of self through the creative activity of consciousness13
Revealed Religion = Religion in which Spirit is presented in and for itself as a unity of its actual shape and true form of self14
Absolute being = the self-consciousness of Spirit15
Spirit as absolute being, which knows itself as all reality = all truth
Essence = that which has being in itself16 = the spiritual alone = the actual
The true alone = the actual
Spirit = self-supporting, absolute, real being17
Absolute Being = Spirit that is in-and-for-itself, insofar as it is simple eternal substance18
Science = the Spirit that knows itself as Spirit19
The way to science = the science of the experience of consciousness20
The description of the coming-to-be of Science as such = the phenomenology of Spirit21
(See also my review of the Phenomenology here.)
FOOTNOTES
1Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A.V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 142.
2Ibid., p. 140.
3Ibid., p. 263.
4Ibid., p. 139.
5Ibid., p. 265.
6Ibid., p. 217.
7Ibid., p. 59.
8Ibid., p. 56.
9Ibid., p. 265.
10Ibid., p. 265.
11Ibid., p. 410.
12Ibid., p. 416
13Ibid., p. 416.
14Ibid., p. 416.
15Ibid., p. 410.
16Ibid., p. 14.
17Ibid., p. 264.
18Ibid., p. 325.
19Ibid., p. 12.
20Ibid., p. 56.
21Ibid., p. 15.
Friday, November 2, 2018
Chronology of the Life of Pauli Murray (1910-1985)
Nov. 20, 1910 – Anna Pauline Murray (she called herself “Pauli”
from about the age of 20 onward1) was born in Baltimore, the fourth
of six children. Her mother, Agnes Fitzgerald Murray, who had been trained as a
nurse at the Hampton Training School for Nurses, died of a cerebral hemorrhage in March 1914, in the fourth month of her seventh
pregnancy, when Pauli was 3 years old. Her father, William Henry Murray, a graduate
of Howard University, was a schoolteacher. However, in 1905, he became ill with
typhoid fever complicated by encephalitis, and he was never mentally the same
afterward.2 In 1917, he had to be committed to the local mental
hospital, and a year later was transferred to Crownsville State Hospital, where
in 1923 he was murdered by a white guard, who beat him to death with a baseball bat.3 The guard was convicted of manslaughter, and was sent to prison for ten years.4
1914 – Pauli went to live with her aunt, Pauline Fitzgerald
Dame, in Durham, North Carolina.
1926 – When Pauli was 16, she graduated from Hillside High
School in Durham, and then moved to New York City to stay with her cousin
Maude. In order to meet the entrance and residency requirements for Hunter
College, which at that time was a women’s college that offered free tuition to
city residents, she spent a year at Richmond Hills High School, graduating in
1927.
1930 – She married William Roy Wynn, but soon realized the
marriage was a mistake, and they permanently separated. The marriage was finally
annulled in 1949.
1933 – She graduated from Hunter College, one of four black
women in a class of 247 women.
1937 – After the decline of a close relationship between her
and Margaret (Peggie) Holmes, whom she had met in 1934, she suffered an
emotional breakdown. She struggled with her transgender identity—she identified as a man in a woman’s body who was attracted to women.5 She was never
able to publicly disclose or discuss her gender identity.
1938 – After she recovered, she applied to graduate school in sociology at the
University of North Carolina, where her white great-great-grandfather had been
a trustee,6 but she received a rejection letter that said explicitly, “members of your race are not admitted to the University.”7
1940 – Pauli and her friend Adelene McBean were arrested and
jailed in Petersburg, Virginia for refusing to move to the back of a bus, thus
violating state segregation laws.
1941 – Pauli enrolled at Howard University Law School,
graduating in 1944 as the only woman and the top-ranked student in her class.
1943-1944 – She participated with other Howard Law School
students in a series of cafeteria sit-ins, protesting racial segregation in
local cafeterias and restaurants.
1944 – She applied for a post-graduate fellowship at Harvard
University Law School, but received a rejection letter that said explicitly
“you are not of the sex entitled to be admitted to Harvard Law School.”8 (Harvard Law School did not admit women as students until 1950.)
1945 – She earned a master’s degree in law from the
University of California, Berkeley. After passing the state bar exam in
1945, she became California's first black deputy attorney general in January
1946.
1950 – She published States’
Laws on Race and Color, an extensive compilation of the laws of every state
regarding racial segregation and discrimination. The book provided a valuable
resource for the NAACP in its struggle against racial discrimination, and Thurgood
Marshall, who was at that time NAACP Chief Counsel, described the book as the “bible” of the civil
rights movement.9
1956 – Her biography of her family, Proud Shoes: The Story of an
American Family, was published.
1956-1960 – She worked as an associate attorney for the New
York law firm of Paul, Weiss, Rifkind, Wharton & Garrison, where she met Irene (Renee) Barlow, office manager, who became her close friend
and companion.
1960-1961 – She taught at the University of Ghana School of
Law, in Accra. She later coauthored with Leslie Rubin a work entitled The Constitution and Government of Ghana
(1964).
1961 – She was appointed by President Kennedy to the
President’s Commission on the Status of Women, serving from 1961-1963.
1963 – On Nov. 14th, she delivered an address
entitled “The Negro Woman in the Quest for Equality” to the National Council of
Negro Women, in Washington, D.C., in which she criticized civil rights leaders
for having failed to invite any women to deliver speeches at the March on
Washington or to be a part of the delegation of leaders that met with President
Kennedy at the White House afterward. She used the term “Jane Crow” for the twofold kind of discrimination that women of color are confronted with—discrimination not only on
the basis of race (Jim Crow), but also on the basis of gender (Jane Crow).
1965 – She coauthored with Mary O. Eastwood an article in the
George Washington Law Review entitled
“Jane Crow and the Law: Sex Discrimination and Title VII.”10
1965 - She became the first African American to earn a
doctoral degree from Yale University Law School. Her doctoral thesis was
entitled “Roots of the Racial Crisis: Prologue to Policy.”
1966 – She was a cofounder of the National Organization for
Women.
1967-1968 – She served as Vice-President of Benedict College
in Columbia, South Carolina.
1970 – She published a collection of her poetry, entitled Dark Testament and Other Poems.
1971 – Ruth Bader Ginsburg, who wrote the plaintiff’s brief
in the U.S. Supreme Court case Reed v.
Reed, named Pauli Murray and Dorothy Kenyon as coauthors, in recognition of
their influential work on gender discrimination. Reed V. Reed was the first case in which the U.S. Supreme Court
ruled that the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment prohibits
gender discrimination.
1968-1973 – Pauli taught at Brandeis University, where she eventually
received tenure as full professor in American Studies.
1973 – Irene Barlow, her longtime friend and companion, died of a brain tumor. Pauli decided to resign her professorship at Brandeis in
order to enter General Theological Seminary in New York and study for the
ministry.
1976 – She completed the third year of her seminary training
at Virginia Theological Seminary, in Alexandria, Virginia, and received a
Master of Divinity degree. Her master’s thesis was later published as “Black
Theology and Feminist Theology: A Comparative Review” (in the Anglican Theological Review, January
1978, pp. 3-24). She described the strengths and weaknesses of black theology
and feminist theology, and suggested that neither had yet fully explored the
interlocking relation between racism, sexism, and classism.
1977 – She was among the first group of women to be ordained
as Episcopal priests (on January 8th, at the Washington National
Cathedral), and was the first African American woman to be ordained as an
Episcopal priest. She had been raised in the Episcopal Church in Durham, North
Carolina, and her aunts Pauline and Sallie had been longtime members of St.
Titus’ Episcopal Church in Durham.
1977 – On June 12th, in a sermon at the Church of
the Holy Comforter in Washington, D.C., she said,
“Jesus of Nazareth…treated women as
persons of equal dignity and worth with men…When he visited the home of Mary
and Martha in Bethany, he approved of Mary’s rejection of the kitchen role and
permitted her to sit at his feet and listen to his teaching as if she were a
male rabbinical student. And when he was teaching in the temple, he refused to
condemn the woman charged with being caught in the act of adultery, saying to
the man who had brought her in, “Let him who is without sin among you cast the
first stone.”…
And women responded as disciples of
Jesus, following him as he went about preaching the good news of the kingdom of
God and using their own means to provide for him and his company. They followed
him to the cross and stood by him during those agonizing hours of crucifixion when
the other disciples had run away in fear. Women discovered the resurrection on
Easter morning and went to tell the eleven; and according to John’s Gospel, Mary
of Magdala was the first person to whom the Risen Lord appeared…
The message of Jesus of Nazareth was
that wholeness of being lies, not in superior status or exclusiveness…but in
the ministry of love and service that recognizes human worth. And many women
today, responding to that message, are seeking a theology which in symbol and
language will help people to understand the wholeness of God and the oneness of
humankind.”11
1977 – On Oct. 12th, in a lecture at Vassar
College, she said,
“My own quest for freedom of self-expression and wholeness
of personality in the face of severe societal restrictions imposed upon me by poverty
in my youth, by racism, and sexism have had much to do with my interest in law
and theology. In my earliest youth I sought to work out intolerable
frustrations through poetry. As I became more deeply involved in the civil
rights movement in the 1940s, I turned to law as a means of working within the
system for social change. In time, as the world crisis has deepened, I began to
realize that the law by itself is inadequate to cope with fundamental moral and
ethical issues of our time, and this led me to theology. I cannot pretend that
I have found a synthesis, for my feminist outlook sharpens the tensions
experienced in trying to come to terms with a continuous struggle for authentic
selfhood...The synthesis that I strive for is one that harnesses the creative
urge to a vision of a more humane society and in which I can direct whatever
talents I possess toward making that vision a reality.”12
1978 – She served as priest in several parishes in
Washington, D.C., Baltimore, and Pittsburgh, but had to retire at age 72, due to
church rules regarding retirement.
1979 – On March 28th, in a lecture at the Church of the Atonement, in Washington, D.C., she said,
“True community is based upon equality, mutuality, and
reciprocity. It affirms the richness of individual diversity as well as the
common human ties that bind us together. The marks of a community of faith are
communion, participation, mutual trust, sharing, and fellowship. A community of
faith is both social and sacramental. As Professor Letty M. Russell of Yale
Divinity School defines it, “Communion is participation with Christ in his work
as the representative of God’s love to others, and sharing with his community
in common actions of celebration, reflection and service to the world.” This is
what we do in our Lenten season in a special sense, for following our
celebration of the Holy Eucharist and sharing of a common meal, we reflect
together on how we can respond to world hunger for human dignity as well as
physical sustenance.”13
1985 – She was featured in a segment of Charles Kuralt’s “On
the Road” program on CBS.
1985 – On July 1, at the age of 76, she died of pancreatic
cancer in Pittsburgh. She was buried under the same headstone as Irene Barlow, in Cypress Hills Cemetery, Brooklyn, New York.
1987 – Her autobiography, Song in a Weary Throat: Memoir of an American Pilgrimage was
published.
FOOTNOTES
1Rosalind Rosenberg, Jane Crow: The Life of Pauli Murray (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2017), p. 39.
2Pauli Murray, Song in a Weary Throat: Memoir of an American Pilgrimage (New York:
Liveright Publishing Corporation, 1987), p. 13.
3Ibid.,
p. 72.
4Ibid.,
p. 73.
5Rosalind Rosenberg, Jane Crow: The Life of Pauli Murray, pp. 55-60.
6Ibid.,
p. 4.
7Song in a
Weary Throat, p. 148.
8Ibid.,
p. 310.
9Ibid., p. 373.
10In this groundbreaking article, Murray and
Eastwood explained that the typical excuses or arguments given by employers for gender
discrimination—namely, (1) the argument that, supposedly, women are only temporary workers, because they will leave work to marry and raise children, (2) the argument that
certain customers or clients may prefer to utilize the services of men rather
than women, (3) the argument that men may be physically stronger or have more
physical endurance than women, and (4) the argument that employers may have to
provide separate facilities, such as dressing rooms or restrooms, for women, thus requiring additional expenses on the part of the employer—do
not, according to Title VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, justify gender
discrimination. (Pauli
Murray and Mary Eastwood, “Jane Crow and the Law: Sex Discrimination and Title
VII,” 34 George Washington Law Review,
1965, abridged version in Radical
Feminism, edited by Anne Koedt, Ellen Levine, and Anita Rapone, Times Books,
1973, pp. 165-176.)
11Pauli
Murray, “Sermon, June 12, 1977,” in Pauli
Murray: Selected Sermons and Writings, edited by Anthony B. Pinn
(Maryknoll: Orbis Books, 2006), pp. 67-69.
12Pauli Murray, “Synthesis: Theology, Feminism,
and the Law—The Impact upon a Creative Writer,” in Pauli Murray: Selected Sermons and Writings, pp. 206-207.
13Pauli Murray, “Challenge of Nurturing the
Christian Community in Its Diversity,” in Pauli
Murray: Selected Sermons and Writings, pp. 210-211.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)