Joseph Raz (1939-2022) was an Israeli philosopher who was born in Haifa (which was then in the British Mandate for Palestine), and died in London. He earned a Magister Juris
degree at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem (1963) and a doctoral (DPhil)
degree at Oxford University (1967). He taught at the Hebrew University as a
member of the Law Faculty and Department of Philosophy from 1967-1972, and was
a Fellow and Tutor in Law at Balliol College, Oxford from 1972-1985, becoming
Professor of the Philosophy of Law at Oxford and Fellow of Balliol College from
1985-2006, and then research professor at Oxford from 2006-2009. He was also a professor
at the Law School at Columbia University, and served as a research professor at King’s College London. His books included The
Concept of a Legal System (1970), Practical
Reason and Norms (1975), The
Authority of Law (1979), The Morality
of Freedom (1986), Ethics in the
Public Domain (1994), Engaging Reason
(1999), Value, Respect, and Attachment
(2001), The Practice of Value (2003),
Between Authority and Interpretation
(2009), and From Normativity to
Responsibility (2011).
In Practical Reason and Norms, he describes the kinds of reasons we may
have for our actions. Such reasons may be operative or non-operative,
complete or partial, strong or weak. They may also be first-order or second-order, relative or absolute, exclusionary or non-exclusionary.
According to Raz, we may have, in addition to
reasons for actions, reasons for beliefs, as well as reasons for other moral or social phenomena, such as desires, emotions, attitudes, norms, and institutions. Beliefs may constitute reasons for action, but they may sometimes be
mistaken, and thus we should be guided by the actual facts of a given situation, rather than merely by what we believe are the facts of that
situation.
Reasons may be called operative if
belief in their existence entails a “practical critical attitude” (such that
conclusions about what we ought to do result from valid inferences about the
nature of our duty, and we are in fact motivated by those conclusions), while
they may be called non-operative (or auxiliary) if they do not entail such an
attitude.
Reasons may be called complete if no
other reasons serve as motives for our actions. They may also be called
complete if they would cease to be complete, were any of their constituents to
be omitted.
Reasons may also be relatively
strong or relatively weak, if they override or are overridden by other reasons.
In cases of conflict between reasons, relatively stronger reasons override
relatively weaker ones.1
While a conclusive reason may be a
reason for which there is no cancelling condition and no other reason that
overrides it, an absolute reason may be a reason for which there couldn’t
possibly be some other reason that would override it. A prima facie reason may be a reason that
is neither conclusive nor absolute.2
While a first-order reason may be a
reason for action, a second-order reason may be a reason to act for some other
reason or to refrain from acting for some other reason.3 While
conflicts between first-order reasons may be resolved by considering the
relative strength of the conflicting reasons, this isn’t the case with
conflicts between first- and second-order reasons.4
An exclusionary reason, says Raz, is a (second-order) reason to refrain from acting for some reason, while a
non-exclusionary reason is not a (second-order) reason to refrain from acting
for some reason.5 In conflicts between first- and second-order
reasons, exclusionary reasons always prevail, since they exclude acting for
those first-order reasons, but the scope of exclusionary reasons depends on the
class of first-order reasons that they exclude.6 Exclusionary reasons may
in some cases be overridden by other second-order reasons.
Decisions may be both first-order
and second-order reasons, insofar as they may be both reasons to act and reasons
to refrain from acting for other reasons. Once they have been made, decisions may
be exclusionary insofar as they exclude further consideration of
alternatives, but they may sometimes be revised or reversed if alternatives are
indeed further considered.
Mandatory norms (such as rules and
principles) are also first- and second-order reasons, insofar as they
are complied with only if they are regarded as valid reasons for action and valid
reasons for disregarding conflicting reasons for action. Thus, “The first-order
strength of a norm depends on…the strength of the reasons for the norm, which
are reasons for doing what is required by the norm.”7 The
second-order (exclusionary) strength of a norm depends on the strength of the
reasons for excluding further consideration of other norms or other reasons for
action.
Non-mandatory norms (such as permissions and power-conferring norms) are also first- and second-order
reasons. Exclusionary permissions (permissions to disregard reasons
for refraining from particular actions) are different from exclusionary reasons (reasons
to refrain from considering other reasons for performing those actions) insofar as they do not
necessarily entail disregard of the excluded reasons; they merely permit it.8
On the other hand, exclusionary permissions are like exclusionary reasons
insofar as they may vary in scope (i.e. in the class of reasons they exclude).9
FOOTNOTES
1Joseph Raz, Practical
Reason and Norms (London: Hutchinson & Co. Ltd., 1975), p. 25.
2Ibid.,
p.27.
3Ibid.,
p.39.
4Ibid.,
p.36.
5Ibid.,
p.39.
6Ibid.,
pp. 40-46.
7Ibid.,
p.77.
8Ibid.,
p.90.
9Ibid.,
p.91.