Is the subject of race inescapable for the black
philosopher? Must every black philosopher be expected to say something about or be an “expert” on the subject of race? Must philosophy for the black
philosopher be self-reflexive, so that his/her/their own blackness, and the meaning of
that blackness in relation to society, must become the subject of his/her/their philosophy? What obligation does the black philosopher have to be socially and
politically engaged? Must philosophy for the black philosopher entail political
activism? Can the black philosopher only engage in “real” philosophy after
he/she/they has/have discovered what it means for him/her/them to be black?
Saturday, April 5, 2014
Saturday, March 15, 2014
The Dalai Lama visits the Washington National Cathedral, 2014
Last Friday, March 7, my wife and I were able to attend an address given by His Holiness, the Dalai Lama, at the National Cathedral in Washington D.C. We were also able to shake hands with His Holiness afterward. It was a very moving experience.
The occasion was entitled "Beyond Religion: Ethics for the Whole World," but the actual theme of the Dalai Lama's message was that all the major religious traditions share an emphasis on love and compassion, on tolerance and forgiveness. The theme of the message was also that, rather than being preoccupied with the differences between religions, cultures, and societies, we should affirm the values that we share as human beings.
Here is a more detailed account, on the website of the Office of His Holiness, of what he said to the audience.
Saturday, February 22, 2014
"Seeing to it" as a Principle of Moral Conduct
Of what significance to moral conduct is the ability to see to (attend to, keep in mind) some task or duty that we’ve been assigned? To what extent does compliance with duty depend on the ability to “see to” some particular action’s being performed or some particular event’s taking place?
If I say that I’ll "see to" some action A’s being performed or some event E’s taking place, then I acknowledge my responsibility to attend to the conditions that will lead to A or E, and I imply that I’ll act with a reasonable amount of care, attentiveness, and diligence in order to ensure that A is performed or that E takes place.
If I say that I’ll "see to" something, then I also imply that I’ll follow through on "seeing to it," and that I’ll make sure, to the best of my ability, that it is actualized or brought to fruition.
“Seeing to it” may therefore fulfill a promise, pledge, or vow to take care of something. It may also be a “seeing that” something is fulfilled or takes place.
"Seeing to" something may represent a mode of "being addressed" to that thing. If we "see to" something, then we pay attention to it, and we address ourselves to ensuring its actualization or coming into being.
However, there may be a practical limit to the number of things that we can attend to within a finite time frame. If we are obligated to attend to many different things at the same time, then we may have to prioritize them, so that we can deal with our most pressing and urgent obligations before we attend to less pressing and less urgent ones.
“Seeing to it” that some action A is performed or that some event E takes place may also fulfill a directive or command that must in some cases be prioritized or structured in relation to other directives or commands.
If I say to someone who has
a right to expect me to be reliable that I’ll see to it that A is performed or that
E takes place, then I may be held blameworthy if I fail to see to it that A is
performed or that E takes place.
Of course, I can only properly be said
to have seen to something if I've acted in such a way that I've ensured its taking
place. If I did nothing to ensure its taking place, then I cannot properly be
said to have seen to it. The action or event in question need not have taken
place solely due to my intervention, but I must have done something to ensure
that it would indeed take place. I must therefore have been in a position
of causal agency in relation to it, so that my seeing to it ensured, or could have ensured, that it took place.1
Nuel Belnap, Michael Perloff, and
Ming Xu (2001) explore the formal semantics of “stit sentences” (sentences in which a subject or agent sees to it
that something is true) as a means of investigating the causal structure of
agency and action. They explain that the stit
sentence “α sees
to it that Q,” where α is an agent and Q is any declarative sentence guaranteed to be true by a prior
choice of action on the part of α,
may be symbolized as [α stit: Q].2
Similarly, they explain that the
sentence “α is
obligated to see to it that Q” may be symbolized as Oblg:[α stit: Q], the sentence “α is forbidden to see to it
that Q” may be symbolized as Frbn:[α stit: Q], and the sentence “α is permitted to see to it that Q” may be symbolized as Perm:[α stit: Q].3
To these sentences may be added their corresponding negations, in order to express other deontic modalities of "seeing
to it" or of "not seeing to it" that Q. Thus, “α is not obligated to see to it that Q” may be symbolized as ~Oblg:[α stit: Q], “α is not forbidden to see to it
that Q” may be symbolized as ~Frbn:[α stit: Q], and “α is not permitted to see
to it that Q” may be symbolized as ~Perm:[α stit: Q].
To these sentences may also
be added the sentence Ought:[α stit: Q] (“α ought to see to it that Q”), and its negation ~Ought:[α stit: Q] (“α ought not to see to it that Q”).
Direct or indirect obligation and
permission to "see to it" that Q may also be expressed by such sentences as: Oblg:[β stit: [α stit: Q] ] (which may be read as "β is obligated to see to it that α sees to it that Q"), and Perm:[β stit: [α stit: Q] ] (which may be read as "β is permitted to see to it that α sees to it that Q"). Similarly, the absence of such obligation
or permission may be expressed by such sentences as ~Oblg:[β stit: [α stit: Q] ] (which may be read as "β is not obligated to see to it
that α sees to it that Q") and ~Perm:[β stit: [α stit: Q] ] (which may be read as "β is not permitted to see to it
that α sees to it that Q").
Belnap, Perloff, and Xu explain that
stit sentences may be used to express
such deontic equivalences as
• Frbn:[α stit: Q] ↔ ~Perm:[α stit: Q]
and
and
• Perm:[α stit: Q] ↔ ~Frbn:[α stit: Q].4
In addition to these, we might take note of such equivalences as
• Oblg:[α stit: Q] ↔ ~Perm:[~α stit: Q]
• Perm:[~α stit: Q] ↔ ~Oblg:[α stit: Q]
• ~Frbn:[α stit: Q] ↔ ~Oblg:[~α stit: Q]
• Perm:[α stit: P ∧ Q] ↔
Perm:[α stit: P] ∧ Perm:[α stit: Q]
Perm:[α stit: P] ∧ Perm:[α stit: Q]
• Ought:[α stit: P ∧ Q] ↔
Ought:[α stit: P] ∧ Ought:[α stit: Q]
Ought:[α stit: P] ∧ Ought:[α stit: Q]
• Oblg:[α stit: P ∧ Q] ↔
Oblg:[α stit: P] ∧ Oblg:[α stit: Q]
Oblg:[α stit: P] ∧ Oblg:[α stit: Q]
and such axioms as
• [α stit: P ∧ Q] →
[ [α stit: P] ∧ [α stit: Q] ]
[ [α stit: P] ∧ [α stit: Q] ]
• [α stit: [P → Q] ] →
[ [α stit: P] → [α stit: Q] ]
[ [α stit: P] → [α stit: Q] ]
• Perm:[α stit: P] ∧ [ [α stit: P] →
Perm:[α stit: Q] ] → Perm:[α stit: Q]
(“if α is permitted to see to it that P, and if in seeing to it that P, α is permitted to see to it that Q, then α is permitted to see to it that Q”)
Perm:[α stit: Q] ] → Perm:[α stit: Q]
(“if α is permitted to see to it that P, and if in seeing to it that P, α is permitted to see to it that Q, then α is permitted to see to it that Q”)
• ~Perm:[α stit: P] ∧ Oblg: [ [α stit: Q] →
[α stit: P] ] → ~Perm:[α stit: Q]
(“if α is not permitted to see to it that P, and if in seeing to it that Q, α is obligated to see to it that P, then α is not permitted to see to it that Q”), and
[α stit: P] ] → ~Perm:[α stit: Q]
(“if α is not permitted to see to it that P, and if in seeing to it that Q, α is obligated to see to it that P, then α is not permitted to see to it that Q”), and
• Oblg:[α stit: P] ∧ [ [α stit: P] →
Oblg:[α stit: Q] ] → Oblg:[α stit: Q]
(“if α is obligated to see to it that P, and if in seeing to it that P, α is obligated to see to it that Q, then α is obligated to see to it that Q”).
Oblg:[α stit: Q] ] → Oblg:[α stit: Q]
(“if α is obligated to see to it that P, and if in seeing to it that P, α is obligated to see to it that Q, then α is obligated to see to it that Q”).
Interestingly, Belnap, Perloff, and Xu distinguish between
“not seeing to it" that Q and “refraining from seeing to it" that Q. Refraining
from seeing to it that Q entails not seeing to it that Q, but not seeing to it
that Q does not entail refraining from seeing to it that Q.5
“Seeing to it that Q” may be
paraphrased as “taking care that Q” or “taking the time to ensure that Q” or “exerting
oneself sufficiently to make sure that Q” (to suggest just a few possible
interpretations). Thus, the sentence “See to it that you knock before you open
the door” may be paraphrased as “Be sure to knock before you open the door”
or “Be careful to knock before you open the door” or “Take time to knock before
you open the door.”
The U.S. Constitution, Article Two,
Section Three, says that the President “shall take care that the laws be
faithfully executed, and shall commission all the officers of the United
States.” Under the "Take Care Clause," the President is therefore obligated to see to it that all laws are faithfully executed, and he/she does not have the power to disregard laws or to allow them to be disregarded. Thus, the responsibility to see to it that the laws are faithfully
executed may require some degree of care, attentiveness, and diligence on the part of the President.
“Seeing to it” may be the basis
of an “ethics of care.” If we see to the health, safety, and well-being of an individual, or of a group of individuals, then we attend to, are responsive to, and
care for his/her/their emotional and physical needs. Our caring for
an individual, or for a group of individuals, may be expressed by our “seeing to” the
actualization of those conditions that promote his/her/their health, safety,
and well-being.
“Seeing to” something may thus require
a kind of moral vision, which may be characterized by not only the capacity to perceive
and appreciate the moral dimensions of human conduct, but also the capacity to feel and communicate a
sense of moral responsibility, the capacity to honor and fulfill moral duties and obligations, and the capacity to promote moral and social understanding.
Moral vision may be a vision of the way in which moral values can be reflected by individuals, institutions, and society.
FOOTNOTES
1Nuel Belnap, Michael Perloff, and Ming Xu
explain that the assignment of moral or legal responsibility to an agent for doing something presupposes that the agent actually did something, and it also presupposes that the agent could have done otherwise. (Facing the Future: Agents and Choices in Our Indeterminist World, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001, p. 256.)
explain that the assignment of moral or legal responsibility to an agent for doing something presupposes that the agent actually did something, and it also presupposes that the agent could have done otherwise. (Facing the Future: Agents and Choices in Our Indeterminist World, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001, p. 256.)
2Belnap, Perloff, and Xu, Facing the Future, p. 6.
3Ibid.,
p. 17.
4Ibid.,
p. 64.
5Ibid.,
p. 41.
Saturday, October 12, 2013
Non-Propositional Language
In the Tractatus, Wittgenstein says, “The totality of propositions is the language” (Prop. 4). But it may be argued, to the contrary, that language does not consist exclusively of propositions, and that language includes both propositional and non-propositional expressions (take, for example, emotive expressions that express feelings or emotions, but not propositions).
Interjections such as “Oops!”, “Holy cow!”, and “Wow!” may be examples of non-propositional expressions. Such expressions may be meaningful without being true or false.
Non-propositional speech-acts include rote recitations of numbers, times, and dates, repetitions of filler words or phrases such as "uh" and "y'know what I mean," conventional greetings such as “Hello” and “Good morning,” expletives such as "Gee whiz!" and “Damn!", and questions such as “How are you?” and “What is that?”.1
Interjections such as “Oops!”, “Holy cow!”, and “Wow!” may be examples of non-propositional expressions. Such expressions may be meaningful without being true or false.
Non-propositional speech-acts include rote recitations of numbers, times, and dates, repetitions of filler words or phrases such as "uh" and "y'know what I mean," conventional greetings such as “Hello” and “Good morning,” expletives such as "Gee whiz!" and “Damn!", and questions such as “How are you?” and “What is that?”.1
Can language be meaningful without expressing propositional attitudes or having a propositional content?
While propositional attitudes2 such as believing, knowing, hoping, desiring, fearing, or remembering that p (where p is a proposition) take a stand or have a bearing as to whether p is or is not the case (or as to whether p ought to or ought not to be the case), non-propositional attitudes take no such stand and have no such bearing. Are there indeed such non-propositional attitudes? Are all cognitive attitudes propositional in form and content?
Is all thinking propositional in nature? If not, then is there some non-propositional language capable of expressing non-propositional thought? Can linguistic signs or symbols express purely intuitive or non-conceptual thinking?
While propositional attitudes2 such as believing, knowing, hoping, desiring, fearing, or remembering that p (where p is a proposition) take a stand or have a bearing as to whether p is or is not the case (or as to whether p ought to or ought not to be the case), non-propositional attitudes take no such stand and have no such bearing. Are there indeed such non-propositional attitudes? Are all cognitive attitudes propositional in form and content?
Is all thinking propositional in nature? If not, then is there some non-propositional language capable of expressing non-propositional thought? Can linguistic signs or symbols express purely intuitive or non-conceptual thinking?
Consider Russell’s example of a non-denoting phrase, “the present king of France.”3 If the sentence, “The present king of France is bald,” is neither true nor false because the phrase “the present king of France” doesn’t denote or refer to anything, then the sentence doesn't express a proposition. But isn’t the sentence still in some way meaningful? Isn’t the sentence a counter-example to Wittgenstein’s thesis that “The totality of propositions is the language”?
FOOTNOTES
1Chris Code, “Speech Automatism and Recurring Utterances,” in The Characteristics of Aphasia, edited by Chris Code (Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1991), p. 158.
2Bertrand Russell, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth [1940] (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1962), p. 18.
3Bertrand Russell, “On Denoting,” in Mind, 14 (1905): 479-493.
ADDITIONAL REFERENCES
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus [1922], translated by C.K. Ogden (Mineola: Dover Publications, 1999).
Sunday, September 22, 2013
Recommended Philosophy Videos
Linda Martín Alcoff, 2012 Presidential Address, APA, Eastern Division
Mark Alfano and Abrol Fairweather, on virtue epistemology
Mark Alfano, "The Logic of Communities of Trust"
Danielle Allen, "Education and Equality"
Corey Anton, "Some Basic Characteristics of Language"
Corey Anton, "Language, Thought & Time"
Corey Anton, "Defining Language? Please Respond"
Corey Anton, "Boundaries between Books and Minds"
Corey Anton, "On Being a Reader"
Mark Alfano and Abrol Fairweather, on virtue epistemology
Mark Alfano, "The Logic of Communities of Trust"
Danielle Allen, "Education and Equality"
Corey Anton, "Some Basic Characteristics of Language"
Corey Anton, "Language, Thought & Time"
Corey Anton, "Defining Language? Please Respond"
Corey Anton, "Boundaries between Books and Minds"
Corey Anton, "On Being a Reader"
John Berger and Susan Sontag, "To Tell a Story"
Elizabeth Camp, "Footnotes, Asides, and Talking Under the Table"
James Cargile, "Philosophy of Logic"
Carneades.org
The Euthyphro Dilemma
The Gettier Problem
In Defense of the Gettier Problem
Properties of Relations
Mereology
Necessary and Sufficient Conditions
Russell's Paradox
De Re vs De Dicto Distinction
Syntactically De Re vs Syntactically De Dicto
Semantically De Re vs Semantically De Dicto
Modally De Re vs Modally De Dicto
Propositional and Categorical Logic
Symbols and Terms (Predicate Calculus)
Bayesian Epistemology
Bayes' Theorem and the Monty Hall Fallacy
Mazviita Chirimuuta, "Color in the Scientific Image"
Stephen Darwall, "Making the "Hard" Problem of Moral Normativity Easier"
Jacques Derrida, "What Comes Before the Question?"
James Cargile, "Philosophy of Logic"
Carneades.org
The Euthyphro Dilemma
The Gettier Problem
In Defense of the Gettier Problem
Properties of Relations
Mereology
Necessary and Sufficient Conditions
Russell's Paradox
De Re vs De Dicto Distinction
Syntactically De Re vs Syntactically De Dicto
Semantically De Re vs Semantically De Dicto
Modally De Re vs Modally De Dicto
Propositional and Categorical Logic
Symbols and Terms (Predicate Calculus)
Bayesian Epistemology
Bayes' Theorem and the Monty Hall Fallacy
Mazviita Chirimuuta, "Color in the Scientific Image"
Stephen Darwall, "Making the "Hard" Problem of Moral Normativity Easier"
Jacques Derrida, "What Comes Before the Question?"
Robin DiAngelo, "Deconstructing White Privilege"
Ronald Dworkin, "Law and Political Morality"
John David Ebert, "Schelling's First Outline of a System of the Philosophy of Nature"
Miranda Fricker, "Moral Philosophy"
Ronald Dworkin, "Law and Political Morality"
John David Ebert, "Schelling's First Outline of a System of the Philosophy of Nature"
Miranda Fricker, "Moral Philosophy"
Helen Frowe, "Reductive Individualism and the Just War Framework"
Paul Fry, "Introduction to Theory of Literature"
1. Introduction
2. Introduction (cont.)
3. Ways In and Out of the Hermeneutic Circle
4. Configurative Reading
5. The Idea of the Autonomous Artwork
6. The New Criticism and Other Western Formalisms
7. Russian Formalism
8. Semiotics and Structuralism
9. Linguistics and Literature
10. Deconstruction I
11. Deconstruction II
12. Freud and Fiction
13. Jacques Lacan in Theory
14. Influence
15. The Postmodern Psyche
16. The Social Permeability of Reader and Text
17. The Frankfurt School of Critical Theory
18. The Political Unconscious
19. The New Historicism
20. The Classical Feminist Tradition
21. African-American Criticism
22. Post-Colonial Criticism
23. Queer Theory and Gender Performativity
24. The Institutional Construction of Literary Study
25. The End of Theory? Neo-Pragmatism
26. Reflections; Who Doesn't Hate Theory Now?
Stephen Fry and Hugh Laurie, "The Subject of Language"
Julia Galef, "What is 'Rationality'?"
Paul Fry, "Introduction to Theory of Literature"
1. Introduction
2. Introduction (cont.)
3. Ways In and Out of the Hermeneutic Circle
4. Configurative Reading
5. The Idea of the Autonomous Artwork
6. The New Criticism and Other Western Formalisms
7. Russian Formalism
8. Semiotics and Structuralism
9. Linguistics and Literature
10. Deconstruction I
11. Deconstruction II
12. Freud and Fiction
13. Jacques Lacan in Theory
14. Influence
15. The Postmodern Psyche
16. The Social Permeability of Reader and Text
17. The Frankfurt School of Critical Theory
18. The Political Unconscious
19. The New Historicism
20. The Classical Feminist Tradition
21. African-American Criticism
22. Post-Colonial Criticism
23. Queer Theory and Gender Performativity
24. The Institutional Construction of Literary Study
25. The End of Theory? Neo-Pragmatism
26. Reflections; Who Doesn't Hate Theory Now?
Stephen Fry and Hugh Laurie, "The Subject of Language"
Julia Galef, "What is 'Rationality'?"
Julia Galef, "The Sunk Costs Fallacy"
Christopher Gauker, on Language, Meaning, and Logic
Tamar Gendler and Eric Schwitzgebel, on implicit associations and belief
Christopher Gauker, on Language, Meaning, and Logic
Tamar Gendler and Eric Schwitzgebel, on implicit associations and belief
Dana Gioia, "What is Poetry? 10 Observations about the Art"
Elizabeth Grosz, Keynote Address at the 2007 Feminist Theory Workshop
Elizabeth Grosz, Keynote Address at the 2007 Feminist Theory Workshop
Isabelle Hamley, "Luce Irigaray"
Thich Nhat Hanh, "What is Nirvana?"
Sally Haslanger, "What is a Social Practice?"
Sarah Hentges, "Understanding Race and Ethnicity, Racism, Oppression, and Privilege"
Thich Nhat Hanh, "What is Nirvana?"
Sally Haslanger, "What is a Social Practice?"
Sarah Hentges, "Understanding Race and Ethnicity, Racism, Oppression, and Privilege"
Jennifer Lackey, "The Prison Education Paradox"
Lama Jampa Thaye, "Parting from the Four Attachments"
Lama Jampa Thaye, "Parting from the Four Attachments"
Lama Jampa Thaye, "Clarifying the Vajrayana"
Annabelle Lever, on "Greening Humanity"
Jennifer McWeeny, "Feminist Ontology for the Twenty-First Century"
Charles Mills, "Does Race Exist?"
Charles Mills, "Liberalism and Racial Justice"
Jennifer Nagel, "Epistemic Territory in Conversation"
Jennifer Lisa Vest, "Gyeke. Akan Concept of a Person"
Jennifer Lisa Vest, "Hume. The Idea of the Self," part 1
Jennifer Lisa Vest, "Hume. The Idea of the Self." part 2
Edmond Wright, "Narrative, Perception, Language, and Faith"
Natalie Wynn, "A Transgender Woman Artfully Answers 'Critical Feminist' Questions About Transpeople"
George Yancy, "Ferris Reynolds Lecture"
Naomi Zack, "Applicative Justice, Race, and Mixed Race"
Linda Zagzebski, "Ancient Greek Virtue Ethics"
Annabelle Lever, on "Greening Humanity"
Jennifer McWeeny, "Feminist Ontology for the Twenty-First Century"
Charles Mills, "Does Race Exist?"
Charles Mills, "Liberalism and Racial Justice"
Jennifer Nagel, "Epistemic Territory in Conversation"
Jennifer Nagel, "Closure and Defeat"
Derek Parfit, Full Address to the Oxford Union Society (2015)
Authors@Google: Steven Pinker
Derek Parfit, Full Address to the Oxford Union Society (2015)
Authors@Google: Steven Pinker
Alvin Plantinga, "What are Possible Worlds?"
Thomas Pogge, "Global Justice: What are the Responsibilities of Citizens?"
Ryan Preston-Roedder, "Three Varieties of Faith"
Michael Puett, "On Zhuangzi in Relation to Confucius"
Avital Ronell, in "Examined Life" (2008)
Avital Ronell, "The Telephone Book @ 25"
Thomas Scanlon, "Ethics of Blame"
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language: Section 1
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language: Section 2
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language: Section 3
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language, Section 4
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language, Section 5
Galen Strawson, "What is the Subject-Experience-Content Identity Thesis?"
Thomas Pogge, "Global Justice: What are the Responsibilities of Citizens?"
Ryan Preston-Roedder, "Three Varieties of Faith"
Michael Puett, "On Zhuangzi in Relation to Confucius"
Avital Ronell, in "Examined Life" (2008)
Avital Ronell, "The Telephone Book @ 25"
Thomas Scanlon, "Ethics of Blame"
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language: Section 1
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language: Section 2
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language: Section 3
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language, Section 4
John Searle, interviewed by Bryan Magee, on the Philosophy of Language, Section 5
Galen Strawson, "What is the Subject-Experience-Content Identity Thesis?"
David Thorstad, "Inquiry Under Bounds"
John Turri, "Virtue Epistemology & Intellectual Character"
Shannon Vallor, "AI and the Shrinking Space of Moral Reasons"
Kevin Vanhoozer, "The Turn to Drama: A Proposal for a Sapiential Apologetics"
John Turri, "Virtue Epistemology & Intellectual Character"
Shannon Vallor, "AI and the Shrinking Space of Moral Reasons"
Kevin Vanhoozer, "The Turn to Drama: A Proposal for a Sapiential Apologetics"
Jennifer Lisa Vest, "Gyeke. Akan Concept of a Person"
Jennifer Lisa Vest, "Hume. The Idea of the Self," part 1
Jennifer Lisa Vest, "Hume. The Idea of the Self." part 2
Edmond Wright, "Narrative, Perception, Language, and Faith"
Natalie Wynn, "A Transgender Woman Artfully Answers 'Critical Feminist' Questions About Transpeople"
George Yancy, "Ferris Reynolds Lecture"
Naomi Zack, "Applicative Justice, Race, and Mixed Race"
Linda Zagzebski, "Ancient Greek Virtue Ethics"
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)