The distinguished German philosopher Nicolai Hartmann (1882-1950) investigates the relation between being-there
and being-so in the second part of his Zur
Grundlegung der Ontologie (1935, Toward
the Foundation of Ontology).
The Grundlegung (the Foundation)
is the first of a four-volume series by Hartmann, dealing with ontology. The other volumes of
the series are Möglichkeit und
Wirklichkeit (1938, Possibility and
Actuality), Der Aufbau der realen
Welt (1940, The Construction of the
Real World), and Philosophie der
Natur (1950, Philosophy of Nature). Möglichkeit und Wirklichkeit is the only
one of these volumes that has, as of 2013, been translated into, and published in, English.
The Grundlegung is divided into four parts: (1) Vom Seinenden als Seienden
überhaupt (Of "That Which Is" as "That Which Is," in General), (2) Das
Verhältnis von Dasein und Sosein (The Relation between Being-There and
Being-so), (3) Die Gegebenheit des realen Seins (The Givenness of Real Being),
and (4) Problem und Stellung des idealen Seins (The Problem and Position of
Ideal Being).
Hartmann distinguishes between ways of being, modes of being, and
aspects of being. Ways of being (Seinsweisen) include ideality and reality. Modes
of being (Seinsmodi) include
actuality, possibility, and necessity (and their negative counterparts,
nonactuality, impossibility, and contingency). Aspects of being (Seinsmomenten) include being-so (Sosein) and being-there (Dasein).
Hartmann also distinguishes between being and “that which is,” and thus between the ontological and
ontic dimensions of philosophical inquiry. The difference between being (Sein) and “that which is” (Seiende) corresponds to the difference between truth and the true, actuality and the actual, reality and the real. The
being of “that which is” may have many different particularizations of its way
of being.1
The distinction between being and "that which is" also corresponds to the distinction between being-there and "that which is there" (Daseiende), and between being-so and "that which is so" (Soseiende).
The central question with which ontology is concerned, “What is being qua being?” cannot therefore be confronted without also confronting the question, “What is ‘that which is’ qua ‘that which is’?”
The central question with which ontology is concerned, “What is being qua being?” cannot therefore be confronted without also confronting the question, “What is ‘that which is’ qua ‘that which is’?”
In all of “that which is,” there are aspects of being-there and
being-so.2 Being-there and being-so are interconnected and mutually
complementary aspects of being. There is no being-there without being-so, and no
being-so without being-there.3
The being-there of “that which is” is constituted by the fact “that it
is,” while the being-so of “that which is” is constituted by “what it is,” i.e. by its quiddity. Thus, being-there is the “that,” and
being-so is the “what” of “that which is.”
There is also being-there in
being-so, and being-so in being-there. Being-there “in” something is the
particular form of being-there of all being-so, while being-so is the
being-there of something “in” something. However, being-there and
being-so are not substances in which “that which is” inheres; rather, they are
aspects or "moments" of being.4
Being-there and being-so are indifferent to each other, insofar as it
makes no difference to being-there whether being-so turns out in one way or
another, and insofar as it makes no difference to being-so whether being-there
turns out in one way or another.5 However, being-there and being-so are also not indifferent
to each other, insofar as they are aspects of the same particular being and therefore share the same (ideal or real) way of being. Real being-there is always that of a
real being-so, and real being-so is always that of a real being-there.6
Being-there and being-so can be indifferent to each other only if they belong
to different ontological spheres, i.e. if being-so belongs to the ideal sphere and
being-there belongs to the real sphere, or vice versa.
Hartmann explains that the epistemological basis of the (misleading)
appearance of separation between being-there and being-so is that real being-so may be a
priori or a posteriori knowable, while real being-there is only a posteriori knowable. Thus, the boundary between aprioristic and aposterioristic knowledge
does not correspond to the (apparent) boundary between being-there and being-so.
From real being-so, aprioristic as well as aposterioristic knowledge is possible,
while from real being-there, only aposterioristic knowledge is possible. Conversely, aposterioristic
knowledge is possible from the being-so, as well as from the being-there, of “that
which is,” while aprioristic knowledge is possible only from the being-so of
“that which is.”7
Aprioristic and aposterioristic sources
of knowledge are also ways of givenness of “that which is.”8 Thus,
there is a threefold superimposition of, or boundary relation between, (1) ways
of givenness (aprioristic or aposterioristic) (2) ways of being (ideal or
real), and (3) moments of being (being-there or being-so). Aprioristic knowledge
is possible from ideal being-so, from ideal being-there, and from real
being-so. Aposterioristic knowledge is possible from real being-so, and from real
being-there. Real being-there can only be an object of aposterioristic
knowledge. Ideal being (ideal being-so and ideal being-there) can only be an
object of aprioristic knowledge.9
FOOTNOTES
1Nicolai Hartmann, Zur Grundlegung
der Ontologie, Second Edition (Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1941), pp. 40-41.
2Ibid., p. 92.
3Ibid., p. 128.
4Ibid., p. 134.
5Ibid., p. 112.
6Ibid., p. 114.
7Ibid., pp.
144-145.
8Ibid., p. 145.
9Ibid., p. 148.
No comments:
Post a Comment